=Paper= {{Paper |id=Vol-1341/paper2 |storemode=property |title=Counter-Argumentation and Discourse: A Case Study |pdfUrl=https://ceur-ws.org/Vol-1341/paper2.pdf |volume=Vol-1341 |dblpUrl=https://dblp.org/rec/conf/argnlp/AfantenosA14 }} ==Counter-Argumentation and Discourse: A Case Study== https://ceur-ws.org/Vol-1341/paper2.pdf
               Counter-Argumentation and Discourse: A Case Study

               Stergos Afantenos                                        Nicholas Asher
              IRIT, Univ. Toulouse                                       IRIT, CNRS,
                     France                                                 France
         stergos.afantenos@irit.fr                                     asher@irit.fr



                      Abstract                              in game theoretic terms it is an equilibrium in a per-
                                                            suasion game in which the addressee adopts an optimal
    Despite the central role that argumentation             action based on the conversational history and in which
    plays in human communication, the compu-                the arguer adopts her conversational strategy based on
    tational linguistics community has paid rela-           the addressee’s strategy for adopting an action (Glazer
    tively little attention in proposing a method-          and Rubinstein, 2004). Yet, despite its importance in
    ology for automatically identifying arguments           human communication and behavior and despite the
    and their relations in texts. Argumentation             fact that textual realizations of arguments and debates
    is intimately related with discourse structure,         are numerous on the web, it is surprising that this area
    since an argument often spans more than one             has received very little attention by the Computational
    phrase, forming thus an entity with its own             Linguistics community.
    coherent internal structure. Moreover, argu-               One domain of research in Computational Linguis-
    ments are linked between them either with a             tics that is of particular interest for argumentation is
    support, an attack or a rebuttal relation. Those        that of discourse. In a typical argumentation process,
    argumentation relations are often realized via          which takes the form of a dialogue, every argument
    a discourse relation. Unfortunately, most of            has an internal coherence meaning that it can be repre-
    the discourse representation theories use trees         sented by a discourse graph. Moreover arguments are
    in order to represent discourse, a format which         linked between themselves either with support, attack
    is incapable of representing phenomena such             or rebuttal relations which are realized once again as
    as long distance attachments and crossed de-            discourse relations linking either the whole discourse
    pendencies which are crucial for argumenta-             subgraphs representing the arguments or parts of them.
    tion. A notable exception is Segmented Dis-             Any attempt to automatically extract the argumentation
    course Representation Theory (SDRT) (Asher              structure from a given text cannot afford to ignore dis-
    and Lascarides, 2003). In this paper we show            course. Our goal in this paper is to show how argumen-
    how SDRT can help identify arguments and                tation is intimately involved with discourse structure.
    their relations. We use counter-argumentation           We achieve this by using counter-argumentation (fol-
    as our case study following Apothéloz (1989)           lowing (Apothéloz, 1989; Amgoud and Prade, 2012))
    and Amgoud and Prade (2012) showing how                 as a case study.
    the identification of the discourse structure can          The remainder of this paper is structured as follows.
    greatly benefit the identification of the argu-         In section 2 we present the current work in the so-called
    mentation structure.                                    argumentation mining, the subfield of computational
                                                            linguistics that deals with the automatic extraction of
1   Introduction                                            the argumentation structure from texts. In section 3 we
People use arguments to persuade others to adopt a          tell a few words on discourse and in section 4 we show
point of view or action they find beneficial to their in-   how SDRT (Segmented Discourse Representatuin The-
terests, or alternatively to prevent others from adopt-     ory, (Asher and Lascarides, 2003)) can be applied in a
ing a position or action that they find contrary to their   case study focused on counter-argumentation. In sec-
interests. Of course an agent may find it in her in-        tion 5 we present the future work and we conclude this
terest to convince an interlocutor to adopt a position      paper.
she herself does not believe; for instance, a seller may
want to persuade a buyer that a product is worth more
than she believes it is worth. Because argumentation        2 Argumentation in Computational
involves an interaction between an arguer and an ad-          Linguistics
dressee, it involves game theoretic aspects: it is the
                                                            Despite its general neglect, argumentation has been
means in language for getting an agent to a position        the focus of some work in Computational Linguistics.
of agreement with the position one is advocating, or        Teufel (1999), Teufel and Moens (2002) aim at identi-
fying what they call the argumentative zones of scien-        all classification or a pairwise classification. The fea-
tific articles. The zones they have used include the aim      tures they use are divided into general ones concerning
of the paper, general scientific background, description      all schemes (features reflecting textual surface form) or
of the authors’ previous work, comparison with other          specific ones for each scheme (mostly cue phrases and
works, etc. They are using a naive bayes model trying         patterns).
to classify each sentence into one of the predefined cat-        Cabrio and Villata (2012a; 2012b) take a different
egories using mostly surface features (position, length,      stance. Their goal is to use Dung’s (1995) abstract ar-
etc) and whether the sentence contains title words or         gumentation framework in order to detect a set of ac-
words scoring high in terms of tf.idf .                       cepted arguments from online debates. They extract
    Palau and Moens (2009) have recently attempted ar-        arguments from Debatopedia2 using textual entailment
gumentation mining, or the identification of arguments        techniques. More precisely, if a sentence T entails
in a text. They assume that an argument consists of           another sentence H then they consider that there is a
a series of premises and a conclusion. Premises and           support relation between the two sentences (and thus
conclusions are represented by propositions in the text.      points of views) otherwise there is an attack relation.
Of course, not all propositions in a given text are part      They use the open source software package EDITS3 in
of an argument. In order to tackle the problem of ar-         order to perform textual entailment. In order then to
gumentation mining the authors break it into a series         identify the set of arguments that would be acceptable
of subtasks. Initially they are interested in perform-        by a an external observer the authors use Dung’s (1995)
ing a binary classification of each proposition into ei-      abstract argumentation framework. In essence an argu-
ther a proposition participating in an argument or not.       ment belongs to the aforementioned set if all the argu-
Propositions that are positively classified are then sent     ments attacking it are rejected. An argument is rejected
to a second classifier which determines whether it is a       if at least one accepted argument attacks it.
premise or a conclusion. For both classification tasks
they use a maximum entropy model and the Araucaria            3 Discourse
corpus1 as well as a corpus extracted from the euro-
                                                              The little prior work on argumentation has ignored dis-
pean court of human rights. The features they use for
                                                              course structure, and we think this is a mistake. A com-
the first classifier include surface features ({1, 2, 3}-
                                                              plete discourse structure of a dialogue will determine
grams, punctuation, sentence and word length), POS
                                                              how each interlocutor’s contribution relates to other
information (adverbs, verbs and modal auxiliaries) and
                                                              contributions, both her own and that of other dialogue
syntactic parsing. The second classifier uses again sur-
                                                              participants. This structure already by itself is crucial
face features, POS tags for the subject and main verb,
                                                              to determining the structure of an argument—which at-
simple rhetorical and argumentative patterns as well as
                                                              tacks are directed towards which other contributions.
the results of the first classifier (although no structured
                                                              Moreover, an argument is not just a sequence of attacks
prediction is attempted which would probably be more
                                                              but a much more complex structure. For one thing, ar-
appropriate, given that the two classifiers are not inde-
                                                              guments contain support moves as well; a good persua-
pendent). Of course, once one has identified the propo-
                                                              sion strategy is to explain why one’s claims are true,
sitions that are premises and conclusions, one does not
                                                              but another is to provide background that will enable
yet have the full arguments. In order to get them, the
                                                              the addressee to understand one’s reasons, and yet an-
authors create a simple CFG grammar which tries to
                                                              other is to provide more details about the claims them-
get the tree structure of arguments. The authors do not
                                                              selves. All of these ”strategies” involve in fact rhetori-
attempt to detect the relations (e.g. support, attack, re-
                                                              cal moves that are different and that may be appropri-
buttal) that connect the arguments between each other.
                                                              ate in different situations. A discourse structure makes
    The Araucaria corpus is used by Feng and Hirst
                                                              plain these different types of moves through the use of
(2011) as well but their goal is not performing ar-
                                                              different discourse relations.
gumentation mining. Instead they focus on the task
                                                                 In effect, discourse structure has the promise to give
of classifying arguments into argumentation schemes
                                                              a much more detailed picture of the nature and struc-
(Walton et al., 2008). Araucaria arguments contain en-
                                                              ture of argumentation. At the moment, we don’t know
thymemes annotated by human subjects which Feng
                                                              exactly what that picture is. But by pursuing the anal-
and Hirst (2011) remove. Moreover, each argument
                                                              ysis of dialogues in terms of argument structure and
is annotated with various argumentation schemes but
                                                              discourse structure we can find out.
the authors keep only the ones that are annotated with
Walton’s schemes. They keep only the 5 more frequent          4 Counter-Argumentation: A Case
schemes. In total they have 393 arguments which they
classify into one of five schemes. Concerning the clas-
                                                                Study
sification method, they use the C4.5 algorithm imple-         To illustrate our point in the previous section, we il-
mented in Weka in order to perform either a one-vs-           lustrate how constructed examples of different sorts of
  1                                                              2
    http://araucaria.computing.dundee.ac.                            http://debatepedia.idebate.org
uk/                                                              3
                                                                     http://edits.fbk.eu
arguments given by Apothéloz (1989) look from a dis-             — [No, she worked hard.]3 [Her eyes have bags
course structure point of view. Apothéloz (1989) iden-           underneath them.]4
tified four different modes of arguing against a given               1
argument. In this work an argument is simply a pair
C(x) : R(y) where R represents the function of reason                  Expl.
and x its content and C the function of conclusion and                2                     3
x its content. x and y can be either propositions, con-                     Correction
                                                                                             Expl.∗
clusions or enthymemes. Given the above, Apothéloz
(1989) distinguishes between four different modes of                                        4
arguing against a given argument C(x):                     (3)    — [Clara works hard]1 [because she is
 1. disputing the plausibility or the truth of a reason,          ambitious.]2
    that is the propositions used in y                            — [It is not out of ambition that Clara works
                                                                  hard.]3 [She is not ambitious.]4
 2. disputing the completeness of the reason                         1
                                                                               Ack.
 3. disputing the relevance of the reason with respect                Expl.
    to the conclusion, and                                            2                     3
                                                                            Correction
 4. disputing the argumentative orientation of the rea-                                      Elab.
    son by showing the reason presented is rather in
                                                                                            4
    favor of the conclusion’s opposite.

Nonetheless, Apothéloz (1989) completely ignores the      In all three examples, the second speaker does not
internal structure that the arguments have. In the fol-    challenge her interlocutor concerning her conclusion
lowing we analyse the different modes of counter-          (EDU 1 in all three cases). In fact, in the example (3)
argumentation that Apothéloz (1989) provides, giving      the second speaker explicitly acknowledges the content
examples found in (Amgoud and Prade, 2012). Our            of the conclusion (Acknowledgment(1, 3)). Instead
goal is to show how discourse analysis can help the        the second speaker’s disagreement is always with the
field of computational linguistics not only detect re-     truth value of the reason behind the conclusion. This
lations between arguments but also analyse the inter-      takes the form of a Correction relation between the
nal structure of an argument. In the following, we are     first speaker’s EDU representing the reason (EDU 2 in
using the Segmented Representation Discourse Theory        all cases) and the second speaker’s counter-argument
(SDRT) (Asher and Lascarides, 2003). For the sake          (EDU 3 for examples (2) and (3) and CDU π1 for ex-
of representation, discourse is represented as a hyper-    ample (1)). For the last two examples the speaker pro-
graph with discourse relations being the edges of the      vides additional reason for her beliefs either by means
graph and Elementary Discourse Units (EDUs) being          of an Elaboration relation or an Explanation∗ rela-
nodes containing only one element, while Complex           tion. This last relation signals an explanation of why b
Discourse Units (CDUs) are nodes containing more           said that Clara worked hard. It is an explanation of a
than one simple elements (Asher et al., 2011).             speech act and provides epistemic grounds for the con-
                                                           tent of the assertion. Note that in all the above exam-
Disputing the plausibility of a reason                     ples the Correction discourse relation amounts to an
When one disputes the plausibility of a reason essen-      attack relation.
tially it amounts to proving that the reason is false.
                                                           Disputing the completeness of a reason
Apothéloz (1989) provides three different ways of
showing that; we illustrate them with the following ex-    In the second mode of counter-argumentation that
amples.                                                    Apothéloz (1989) has identified, the second speaker
                                                           does not attack the truthfulness of the reason but rather
(1)    — [Clara will fail her exams.]1 [She did not        its completeness. Here are some examples.
       work hard]2
       — [Clara?!]3 [She worked non-stop.]4                (4)    — [Clara will fail her exams.]1 [She did not
                                                                  work hard]2
         1                                                        — [Clara will not fail her exams.]3 [She is very
           Expl.                                                  smart.]4
          2                    π1                                          Correction
                                                                     1                      3
                Correction
                                                                          Expl.                 Expl.
                     3                  4                              2                   4
                       Continuation
                                                           In this example, the second speaker neither affirms nei-
(2)    — [Clara will fail her exams.]1 [She did not        ther denies the reason, i.e. the fact that Clara didn’t
       work hard]2                                         work hard. Instead, she is ignoring it (manifested by
the fact that no discourse relation exists between EDUs                π1
2 and 3 or 4). Instead she corrects the conclusion of the
first speaker by providing more evidence which lead to
the contrary. Again, the Correction discourse relation                                       Correction
                                                             1                    2
connects two arguments and serves as an attack argu-                 Expl.
                                                                                      Ack.
mentative relation.
                                                                                  3                               4
(5)    — [Paul is in his office ]1 [because his car is in                                          Contrast
       the carpark.]2
       — [But the car is in the carpark]3 [because it       Here the second speaker acknowledges the reason of
       has a mechanical problem and is undriveable.]4       the first person, as seen by the discourse relation be-
                                                            tween EDUs 2 and 3, but then shows that there is a con-
                                                            trast between this and her conclusion, disagreeing thus
         π1                              π2                 with the whole argument. It is important to note once
                    Correction                              again that in this example, as the preceding ones, the
                                                            discourse analysis enables us to clearly pinpoint which
1                   2          3                     4      elements of the first argument are accepted and which
       Expl.                            Expl.               are attacked by the second speaker.

In this case both arguments (as before) are thor-           (8)    — [Clara will fail her exams.]1 [She did not
oughly supported by an Explanation discourse re-                   work hard]2
lation. Moreover the second speaker even explic-                   — [She will not fail her exams]3 [because she
itly agrees with the reason given by the first one                 did not work hard,]4 [but rather because of the
(Acknowledgment(2, 3)) but she disagrees with the                  stress.]5
whole argument (note the Correction relation be-
tween the two CDUs) since she judges that the reason
                                                                                 Correction
is not enough and provides more evidence (EDU 4) to                   π1                                  3
back her disagreement up.                                                                ¬Expl.
                                                                                                          Expl.
(6)    — [This object is red]1 [since it looks red.]2       1                     2            4                  5
       — [But the object is illuminated by a red                  Explanation                         Contrast
       light.]3
                            Counterevidence                 This is a very interesting example. As the discourse
                   π1                                 3     analysis shows the undirected cycle that is produced
                                                            between EDUs 3, 4 and 5 enables the second speaker to
                                          Contrast          explain why she disagrees with the whole of the initial
           1                       2
                   Expl.                                    statement.

Now, this example is quite more complicated to ana-         Disputing the argumentative orientation of a
lyze. There is a contrast between the object’s looking      reason
red, which generates the expectation that it is red, and    In the final mode of counter-argumentation that
the fact that the object is illuminated by a red light,     Apothéloz (1989) has proposed the second speaker
which would tend to put that expectation in doubt. But      does not dispute neither the reason nor the conclusion.
putting the expectation into doubt also puts into doubt     Instead she argues that the reason corroborates towards
the causal relation supposed by the first speaker be-       the opposite of the conclusion. This can be illustrated
tween 1 and 2.                                              with the following example.

Disputing the relevance of a reason                         (9)    — [Running a marathon is exhausting.]1 [The
In the third mode of counter-argumentation that                    whole body undergoes too much stress.]2
Apothéloz (1989) has identified concerns the second               — [That’s precisely what makes it nice!]3
speaker does not attack the truthfulness or the com-                              Acknowledgment
                                                                               π1                    3
pleteness of a reason but instead its relevance. Be-                                 Correction
low are some examples of this mode of counter-
argumentation.                                                        1                       2
                                                                               Expl.
(7)    — [Clara will fail her exams.]1 [She did not
       work hard]2                                          5 Discussion and Future Work
       — [Indeed, she did not work hard,]3 [but not
       working hard is not a reason to necessarily fail     In the previous section we have showed via the use
       one’s exams.]4                                       of a case study how the use of a discourse represen-
                                                            tation theory can help us represent in fine detail the
phenomena that take place during argumentation—in                                             4
this particular case, counter argumentation during a di-
alogue. In order to represent discourse we have chosen                                1
to use the Segmented Discourse Representation Theory
(SDRT) of Asher and Lascarides (2003). This choice
was made after careful consideration of the phenomena                                                   3
present during argumentation as well as the expressive
power of other discourse representation theories.                                     2
   Take for example the Rhetorical Structure Theory
(RST, Mann and Thompson (1988)), which is the most             where edges with arrows denote support relations and
widely cited and used discourse representation theory          edges with circles denote undercuts. The RST graph
currently. In RST, as in SDRT, the basic units are the         for the above dialogue is the following:
same, namely EDUs.4 In RST adjacent EDUs can
                                                                                 E VIDENCE
be linked together with rhetorical relations in order to
form what in RST’s jargon are called spans. Spans
can be linked with rhetorical relations either with other                ✠
                                                                     E VIDENCE            A NTITHESIS
adjacent EDUs or adjacent spans. We keep on em-                    ✠                            ❘
phasizing the word “adjacent” since this constitutes in            1              2   3           4
our opinion (but see also (Peldszus and Stede, 2013))             As we can see, the structural properties of those two
a limitation of RST since it does not allow this the-          graphs are completely different and the use of RST for
ory to have long distance dependencies, a crucial phe-         argumentative analysis does not seem to be a promis-
nomenon in argumentation. SDRT does not have this              ing path to follow. On the other hand, SDRT neatly
limitation. Consider example (7). In this simple ex-           follows the argumentation graph (we have used the box
ample the Correction relation—which, incidentally, is          representation of SDRT here) making it thus more ap-
the backbone of the second speaker’s attack—holds be-          propriate for use in argumentative analysis.
tween non-adjacent EDUs. Even if the first speaker’s
argument was much longer, or if the second speaker
elaborated on the fact that Clara did not work hard (and             1
                                                                                  Correction            Correction
thus we had many EDUs intervening between π1 and 4)                      Expl.                    3                  4
it wouldn’t influence the fact that the complex segment              2
π1 would be attached to EDU 4. Such long distance
attachments are impossible with SDRT which requires
that each EDU or span is attached to an adjacent EDU
or span.                                                       At this point we would like to say a few words on
   The second problem that RST has as far as the rep-          the computational extraction of discourse structures.
resentation of argumentative structures is concerned, is       Most of the published work currently is using the RST
that it cannot correctly represent rebuttals. This is prob-    framework. This is due to two facts. Firstly there are
lem that is also reported by Peldszus and Stede (2013)         more annotated data available for RST and secondly
so we are using their example, slightly modified in or-        the problem is computationally less demanding since
der to illustrate this point. Consider the following dia-      decisions are always made locally (attachments can be
logue:                                                         either left or right of a given span) which renders this
                                                               framework more simple and thus more attractive to re-
(10)     — [We should tear the building down.]1 [It is         searchers. Of course, this implies that all long distance
         full of asbestos.]2                                   attachements are completely lost, an aspect which is
         — [It is possible to clean it up.]3                   crucial, as we have seen, for argumentation.
         — [But that would be forbiddingly expensi-               Muller et al. (2012) have recently attempted extrac-
         ve!]4                                                 tion of SDRT structures using data from the ANNODIS
                                                               corpus (Afantenos et al., 2012), annotated with SDRT
                                                               structures, with state of the art results. The authors at-
The argumentation graph that results from this dia-            tack the problem of predicting SDRT discourse struc-
logue, according to the scheme proposed in (Peldszus           tures by making some simplifications to the objects that
and Stede, 2013) is the following:                             they need to predict, namely they eliminate CDUs by
    4
      There is a big difference as far as EDUs are concerned   making the assumption that, semantically speaking, at-
between the two theories. In SDRT EDUs can be embedded         tachment to a CDU amounts to attaching to its head—
the one within the other whilst RST does not allow it.         that is the uppermost and leftmost EDU. They have thus
                                                               structures reminiscent of dependency graphs in syntac-
                                                               tic analysis.
                                                                  The authors perform structured prediction on the de-
                                                               pendency graphs they produced which can be broken
down into two steps. Initially they learn local prob-          units and their semantics. In Contstraints in Dis-
ability distributions for attaching and labeling EDUs,         course (CID 2011), Agay-Roches Rouges, France.
based on naive bayes and logistic regression models.
                                                             Elena Cabrio and Serena Villata. 2012a. Combin-
They effectively thus create a complete graph where            ing textual entailment and argumentation theory for
each node represents an EDU and each arc a probabil-           supporting online debates interactions. In Proceed-
ity of attachment. The authors then move on to the de-         ings of the 50th Annual Meeting of the Association
coding phase where the goal is to extract the graph that       for Computational Linguistics (Volume 2: Short Pa-
approaches the reference object. They use two decod-           pers), pages 208–212, Jeju Island, Korea, July. As-
ing approaches based on A∗ and Maximum Spanning                sociation for Computational Linguistics.
Tree (MST) algorithms.
                                                             Elena Cabrio and Serena Villata. 2012b. Natural
                                                               Language Arguments: A Combined Approach. In
Closing this paper we would like to state that one of          20th European Conference on Artificial Intelligence
the main reasons that extraction of argumentative struc-       (ECAI 2012), Montpellier, France.
tures has not been more widely explored by the com-
putational linguistics community is due to the fact that     Phan Minh Dung. 1995. On the acceptability of ar-
few annotated corpora exist. We believe that a project         guments and its fundamental role in nonmonotonic
with the goal of jointly annotating argumentative and          reasoning, logic programming and n-person games.
discourse structures is crucial for the advancement of         Artificial Intelligence, 77:321–357.
this field, as well as other fields such as automatic sum-   Vanessa Wei Feng and Graeme Hirst. 2011. Classi-
marization (Afantenos et al., 2008), question answer-          fying arguments by scheme. In Proceedings of the
ing, etc.                                                      49th Annual Meeting of the Association for Com-
                                                               putational Linguistics: Human Language Technolo-
                                                               gies, pages 987–996, Portland, Oregon, USA, June.
References                                                     Association for Computational Linguistics.
Stergos D. Afantenos, Vangelis Karkaletsis, Panagiotis       Jacob Glazer and Ariel Rubinstein. 2004. On opti-
  Stamatopoulos, and Constantin Halatsis. 2008. Us-            mal rules of persuasion. Econometrica, 72(6):1715–
  ing Synchronic and Diachronic Relations for Sum-             1736, November.
  marizing Multiple Documents Describing Evolving
  Events. Journal of Intelligent Information Systems,        William C. Mann and Sandra A. Thompson. 1988.
  30(3):183–226, June.                                        Rhetorical Structure Theory: Towards a Functional
                                                              Theory of Text Organization. Text, 8(3):243–281.
Stergos Afantenos, Nicholas Asher, Farah Bena-
  mara, Myriam Bras, Cecile Fabre, Mai Ho-Dac,               Philippe Muller, Stergos Afantenos, Pascal Denis, and
  Anne Le Draoulec, Philippe Muller, Marie-Paul                Nicholas Asher. 2012. Constrained decoding for
  Pery-Woodley, Laurent Prevot, Josette Rebeyrolles,           text-level discourse parsing. In Proceedings of COL-
  Ludovic Tanguy, Marianne Vergez-Couret, and                  ING 2012, pages 1883–1900, Mumbai, India, De-
  Laure Vieu. 2012. An empirical resource for discov-          cember. The COLING 2012 Organizing Committee.
  ering cognitive principles of discourse organisation:
                                                             Raquel Mochales Palau and Marie-Francine Moens.
  the annodis corpus. In Nicoletta Calzolari (Con-
                                                               2009. Argumentation mining: The detection, clas-
  ference Chair), Khalid Choukri, Thierry Declerck,
                                                               sification and structure of arguments in text. In Pro-
  Mehmet Uğur Doğan, Bente Maegaard, Joseph Mar-
                                                               ceedings of the 12th International Conference on Ar-
  iani, Jan Odijk, and Stelios Piperidis, editors, Pro-
                                                               tificial Intelligence and Law, ICAIL ’09, pages 98–
  ceedings of the Eight International Conference on
                                                               107, New York, NY, USA. ACM.
  Language Resources and Evaluation (LREC’12), Is-
  tanbul, Turkey, may. European Language Resources           Andreas Peldszus and Manfred Stede. 2013. From ar-
  Association (ELRA).                                          gument diagrams to argumentation mining in texts:
                                                               A survey. International Journal of Cognitive Infor-
Leila Amgoud and Henri Prade. 2012. Can ai models
                                                               matics and Natural Intelligence (IJCINI), 7(1):1–31.
  capture natural language argumentation? Interna-
  tional Journal of Cognitive Informatics and Natural        Simone Teufel and Marc Moens. 2002. Summariz-
  Intelligence, 6(3):19–32, July.                              ing Scientific Articles: Experiments with Relevance
                                                               and Rhetorical Status. Computational Linguistics,
Denis Apothéloz. 1989. Esquisse d’un catalogue des
                                                               28(4):409–445, December.
  formes de la contre-argumentation. Travaux du Cen-
  tre de Recherches Sémiologiques, 57:69–86.                Simone Teufel. 1999. Argumentative Zoning: Infor-
                                                               mation Extraction from Scientific Articles. PhD The-
Nicholas Asher and Alex Lascarides. 2003. Logics of
                                                               sis, University of Edinburgh.
  Conversation. Studies in Natural Language Process-
  ing. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK.            Douglas Walton, Chris Reed, and Fabrizio Macagno.
                                                               2008. Argumentation Schemes. Cambridge Univer-
Nicholas Asher, Antoine Venant, Philippe Muller, and
                                                               sity Press.
  Stergos D. Afantenos. 2011. Complex discourse