=Paper= {{Paper |id=Vol-1364/paper3 |storemode=property |title=Towards a Better Understanding of Critiques about Ancient Texts using Argumentation |pdfUrl=https://ceur-ws.org/Vol-1364/paper3.pdf |volume=Vol-1364 |dblpUrl=https://dblp.org/rec/conf/esws/VillataZ15 }} ==Towards a Better Understanding of Critiques about Ancient Texts using Argumentation== https://ceur-ws.org/Vol-1364/paper3.pdf
    Towards a Better Understanding of Critiques
     about Ancient Texts using Argumentation

                       Serena Villata1 and Arnaud Zucker2
           1
               INRIA Sophia Antipolis, France serena.villata@inria.it
                2
                  Univ. Nice Sophia Antipolis, France zucker@unice.fr



      Abstract. Ancient texts are interpreted by critics in order to assign
      them a given semantics. However, the semantics to be associated to
      these texts is not unique and different critics may have different con-
      flicting opinions about their “correct” interpretation. In this paper, we
      propose to adopt argumentation theory, a technique to manage conflict-
      ing information, together with Semantic Web languages and techniques
      to provide an overall view of such conflicting critiques, detect what are
      the different competing viewpoints and what are the strongest arguments
      emerging from the debate. An ontology for argumentative documents is
      used to annotate ancient texts, and an example of such annotation is
      provided about the topic of the Eternity of the species in Aristotle.


1    Introduction

Ancient texts are subject to different interpretations depending on the historical
context of the text, the personal interpretation of the critic writing the critique,
and the literal sense that is associated to the sentences composing the text. In
general, apart from the ecdotic aspects (that is textual criticism), the primary
goal of a critique is to ascertain the text’s primitive or original meaning in
its literal sense and its original historical context. In order to have a better
understanding of the ancient text and the associated critiques, the following
methodologies have been proposed in the literature:

Genre critique : the literary form of the text is analyzed with special attention
   to genre requirements and tradition (e.g., prose vs verse, letters, epics, dialog,
   scientific text, etc.);
Source critique : the search for intertextuality, especially directed to the sources
   which lie behind a canonical text or compilation literature, such as encyclo-
   pedias;
Cultural critique : the study of the historical, social, and intellectual context
   of the text, used to reconstruct the cultural issues at stake and the historical
   meaning of the work;

    These forms of criticism can be adopted or combined to have a clearer un-
derstanding of an ancient text, but one step that is missing is how to deal with
situations where different critics have viewpoints that are in contrast with each




                                         23
other? This is the research question we address in this paper, with the aim to
detect which critiques could be considered compatible with others and to let
emerge competing viewpoints. More precisely, we propose to adopt argumenta-
tion theory, a reasoning technique designed to infer non conflicting conclusions
starting from a set of heterogeneous possibly conflicting arguments. Our proposal
consists in merging argumentation theory as reasoning engine and Semantic Web
languages and techniques to represent such data and extract further interesting
information.
    The combination of these two techniques can actually help in having a better
comprehension of a set of critiques from different sources, supporting in such a
way an informed choice about the kind of interpretation we aim to back up or
to adopt (e.g., in a learning scenario, the fact of providing a clear overall view
of a set of different critiques about a specific ancient text can support students
in constructing a better grasp of such a text).
    The reminder of the paper is as follows: the overall framework we are in
introducing is presented in Section 2, and then some conclusions are drawn
together with a comparison with the related work.


2   The proposed framework

An abstract argumentation framework [4] aims at representing conflicts among
elements called arguments through a binary attack relation. It allows to reason
about these conflicts in order to detect, starting by a set of arguments and the
conflicts among them, which are the so called accepted arguments. The accepted
arguments are those arguments which are considered as believable by an external
evaluator, who has a full knowledge of the argumentation framework. A Dung-
style framework is based on a binary attack relation among arguments, whose
role is determined only by their relation to other arguments.
    Dung [4] presents several acceptability semantics that produce zero, one,
or several sets of accepted arguments. The set of accepted arguments of an
argumentation framework consists of a set of arguments that does not contain
an argument attacking another argument in the set. Roughly, an argument is
accepted if all the arguments attacking it are rejected, and it is rejected if it has
at least an argument attacking it which is accepted. In Figure 1.a, an example
of abstract argumentation framework is shown. The arguments are visualized
as circles, and the attack relation is visualized as edges in the graph. Grey
arguments are the accepted ones. We have that argument a attacks argument b,
and argument b attacks argument c. Using Dung’s acceptability semantics [4], the
set of accepted arguments of this argumentation framework is {a, c}. The need of
introducing also a positive relation among the arguments, i.e., a support relation,
leads to the emergence of the so called bipolar argumentation frameworks [3]. An
example of bipolar argumentation framework is visualized in Figure 1.b where
the dashed edge represents the support relation.
    Our idea consists in i) exploiting argumentation to provide an overall view of
the set of critiques about an ancient text, and ii) to provide a semantic machine




                                         24
                  a         b         c        a       b         c



                 (a)                                   d        (b)


Fig. 1. Example of (a) an abstract argumentation framework, and (b) a bipolar argu-
mentation framework.


readable representation of such argumentative set of possibly conflicting cri-
tiques. In order to address the former step, we adopt bipolar abstract argumenta-
tion theory such that two possible relations among the critiques are highlighted,
i.e., a positive support relation, and a negative conflict relation. Concerning the
second step, in order to not introduce yet another argumentation vocabulary,
we reuse the SIOC Argumentation module [5], focused on the fine-grained rep-
resentation of discussions and argumentations in online communities.1 The SIOC
Argumentation model is grounded on DILIGENT [2] and IBIS2 models. More
precisely, we adopt the extension proposed by Cabrio et al. [1] of the SIOC Argu-
mentation vocabulary where two new properties sioc arg:challengesArg and
sioc arg:supportsArg whose range and domain are sioc arg:Argument. These
properties represent challenges and supports from arguments to arguments, as
required in abstract argumentation theory.3 This needs to be done since in SIOC
Argumentation challenges and supports are addressed from arguments towards
sioc arg:Statement only.
     The following example shows a real instance of ancient text, i.e., the eternity
of the species in Aristotle, how it is annotated using argumentation theory, and
what are the winning arguments we detect.
Example 1. Consider the following five arguments proposed by the critiques
about Aristotelian interpretation of the eternity of the species:
Argument 1 : The biological species are eternal.
   This argument relies on the following assumptions taken out of the Aristotelian
   works:
    – The general Aristotelian conception is that the world is eternal and uncreated,
       and so are the parts of the world, either in number or in another way.
    – A form, consisting logically in the prior cause of everything, can neither be
       created nor destroyed.
    – The species although not being eternal in number are eternal in form.
    – Through generation each organism is reproduced one in form and replicates
       the same form it has received.
    – The final cause of animal is to obtain eternity through reproduction.
    – Any kind of generation presupposes the preexistence of a form that has to be
       transmitted, and this form is transcendent to the individuals.
1
  For an overview of the argumentation models in the Social Semantic Web, see [6].
2
  http://purl.org/ibis
3
  The extended vocabulary can be downloaded at http://bit.ly/SIOC_
  Argumentation




                                          25
    – Even without being fathered (in spontaneous generation) creatures display the
       form of a regular species.
Argument 2 : The species are not eternal.
   This argument relies on the following assumptions:
    – The existence of the form characteristic of members of a kind is contingent on
       members of that species.
    – The form is not fixed since the individuals constantly differs, because the form
       (given by the male) has to struggle with the matter-principle, which is the
       contribution of the female, and it often turns out that the movements of the
       male are dominated and the form damaged and altered by the power of the
       matter-principle.
    – Hybrids are fertile, and the offspring has necessarily a form ; yet they are
       produced by individuals of different species.
    – The species is not a universal type, but a series of historical individuals which
       are the same in form.
Argument 3 : The species do not exist at all as entities or ousiai.
   This argument relies on the following assumptions:
    – Aristotle never gives a definition of an animal, whereas definition is an onto-
       logical requirement for all substances (ousiai).
    – He uses always the word eidos (form/species) relative to something else (and
       not independently).
    – An animal eidos is not a substance (ousia) according to the definition pro-
       vided by Aristotle in Posterior Analytics, where he states that it should have
       predicates ranked in correct order (which is impossible in the case of animal,
       the predicate being simultaneously coordinate and not strictly subordinate).
    – The animal ousia in the biological realm is the concrete individual animal.
Argument 4 : Aristotelian zoology tolerates evolutionary mechanisms.
   This argument relies on the following assumptions:
    – As Aristotle puts it, new kinds arise from fertile hybrids.
    – Continuance of species does not entail fixity.
    – Individuals are generated in an approximation to a “form” of that species but
       never reach the perfect form of a species.
    – There are dualizing organisms such as seals, bats, ostriches, . . . .
    – The offspring offers many differences with its parent.
Argument 5 : In the conceptual frame of Aristotelian biology, the species are fixed.
   This argument relies on the following assumptions:
    – The species exists as such only if it has a hereditary form (genos).
    – The theory of form and formal cause entails that the species coincide with a
       fixed pattern.
    – The only reason (or formal cause) of generation is the replication of a form
       granting living creatures existence.
    – If species were not fixed there would be no possible science of living creatures,
       since science requires permanency and only deals with firm realities.
These arguments are annotated as follows using the extended SIOC-Argumentation
vocabulary, where due to space constraints we show only two assumptions for
each of the two main arguments of the example:
 a sioc_arg:Argument ;
                  sioc:content "The species are eternal." ;
                  sioc_arg:challengesArg  .




                                             26
 a sioc_arg:Argument ;
                  sioc:content "The species are not eternal." ;
                  sioc_arg:challengesArg  .

 a sioc_arg:Statement ;
                  sioc_arg:argues_on  ;
                  sioc:content "The general Aristotelian conception is that the
                  world is eternal and uncreated, and so are the parts of the
                  world, either in number or in another way." .

 a sioc_arg:Statement ;
                  sioc_arg:argues_on  ;
                  sioc:content "The existence of the form characteristic of
                  members of a kind is contingent on members of that species." .

More precisely, the arguments (i.e., the general claims that are raised) are ex-
pressed as sioc arg:Argument, and the statements (i.e., the statements on which
the argument is built) are expressed as sioc arg:Statement. Statements are
linked to their related arguments by the property sioc arg:argues on. The ad-
vantage of using RDF is that the stored information can then be queried using
SPARQL to retrieve further insightful information from the available data. Fi-
nally, Figure 2 shows how the arguments are linked to each other by support
and conflict relations. Using acceptability semantics, we have that different set
of arguments can be accepted together, i.e., either {A1 , A3 , A5 } or {A2 , A3 , A4 }.


                                                    The species are not eternal.

                                                                A2

         The biological species are eternal.

                                                                                       The species are fixed.
                                A1
                                                                                              A5

                A3

   The species do not exist at all
       as entities or ousiai.
                                                                A4

                                               Tolerance of evolutionary mechanisms.



Fig. 2. The complete bipolar argumentation framework resulting from the arguments
proposed in Example 1.


    Note that an argumentation model where only “challenges” and “supports”
are used to represent the relations among the arguments is not sufficient to han-
dle a fine-grained analysis of metaphysical controversies. An example is provided
in Figure 2 where argument A3 is not linked with any of the other arguments
because its relation with them cannot be casted in an attack/support relation.
For this reason, we plan to consider more complex argumentation structures,
namely argumentation schemes, to capture finer grained argument patterns in
controversies.




                                                   27
3   Conclusions
In this paper, we have proposed a framework to have a better understanding
of the critiques about an ancient text by combining argumentation theory and
Semantic Web languages and techniques. There are few works with purposes
similar to our one. Note that the problem here is that what we call an ancient
text is a set of several works (Posterior Analytics, On Generation of Animals,
Metaphysics . . . ). One of them has been proposed by Vasilopoulou-Spitha and
Bikakis [7]. They propose to use argumentation as a tool for the natural rep-
resentation of claims about cultural artifacts and the arguments they are as-
sociated with. This point is shared with our present work. On the other side,
they propose to extend ontology-based models like CIDOC-CRM to integrate
information about the sources of cultural information (e.g. bibliographic data)
enabling users to assess the validity of this information. So, the goal of the two
papers is different even if similar, and the adopted methodology differs as well.
    There are several open issues to be addressed. First of all, we are cur-
rently annotating a dataset of argumentative critiques using the extended SIOC-
Argumentation ontology, so that we can use query languages like SPARQL to
retrieve further interesting information. Second, we will apply our approach to
learning scenarios, where the argumentation graphs of the critiques are used to
detect the winning opinions and analyse them, improving their comprehension
by students. This methodology could be applied also to internal controversies
displayed in ancient texts (such as the question debated by Aristotle in On Res-
piration wether fish breath or not, with conflicting arguments). Third, we need
to adopt natural language processing techniques to automatically extract such
arguments from texts and to detect the relations among them, starting from the
approach presented in [1] and adapting it to such a kind of specific texts.

References
1. E. Cabrio, S. Villata, and F. Gandon. A support framework for argumentative
   discussions management in the web. In Proc. of ESWC, pages 412–426, 2013.
2. A. G. Castro, A. Norena, A. Betancourt, and M. A. Ragan. Cognitive support for
   an argumentative structure during the ontology development process. In Proc. of
   Intl. Protege Conference, 2006.
3. C. Cayrol and M.-C. Lagasquie-Schiex. Bipolarity in argumentation graphs: Towards
   a better understanding. In Proc. of SUM, LNCS 6929, pages 137–148, 2011.
4. P. Dung. On the acceptability of arguments and its fundamental role in non-
   monotonic reasoning, logic programming and n-person games. Artif. Intell.,
   77(2):321–358, 1995.
5. C. Lange, U. Bojars, T. Groza, J. Breslin, and S. Handschuh. Expressing argumen-
   tative discussions in social media sites. In Proc. of SDoW, 2008.
6. J. Schneider, T. Groza, and A. Passant. A review of argumentation for the social
   semantic web. Semantic Web J., 2011.
7. A. Vasilopoulou-Spitha and A. Bikakis. Semantics-based models for the represen-
   tation of claims about cultural artifacts and their sources. In Proc. of AImWD,
   volume 981. CEUR, 2013.




                                        28