=Paper= {{Paper |id=Vol-1419/paper0022 |storemode=property |title=Gender and Generics: What Makes a Gender-specific Generic Sentence True? |pdfUrl=https://ceur-ws.org/Vol-1419/paper0022.pdf |volume=Vol-1419 |dblpUrl=https://dblp.org/rec/conf/eapcogsci/PassanisiH15 }} ==Gender and Generics: What Makes a Gender-specific Generic Sentence True?== https://ceur-ws.org/Vol-1419/paper0022.pdf
      Gender and Generics: What makes a gender-specific generic sentence true?
                                        Alessia Passanisi (alessia.passanisi@unikore.it)
                                       Faculty of Human and Social Sciences, Kore University,
                                             Cittadella Universitaria - 94100 Enna (EN)

                                           James A. Hampton (hampton@city.ac.uk)
                                  Department of Psychology, City University, Northampton Square
                                                    London, EC1V OHB UK



                             Abstract                                       instead of the sentence meaning “everything that is a duck
  Generic statements assert default properties of a kind. They
                                                                            lays eggs,” it means something like “a relevant fact to know
  reflect the relevant features of our concepts and are                     about ducks is that some lay eggs.” Quantifying the
  considered by people generally true of the entire class despite           sentence with “all” may reduce the likelihood that people
  the existence of counterexamples (e.g. birds fly). We report              will judge it to be true, but it does not trigger extensional
  three experiments which explore the factors that lead to the              thinking to any great extent. The truth of generic sentences
  acceptance of generic statements. In particular we examine                depends not on the absence of counterexamples but on what
  whether properties that relate to gender differences (lions               is considered a relevant fact about the kind. For example,
  have manes, or ducks lay eggs) are more likely to be accepted
  than matched statements that refer to an arbitrary subclass               although “Canadians are right-handed” is true of a majority
  unrelated to gender. Experiments 1 and 2 found surprisingly               of Canadians, it is not judged as being generically true
  that gender-specific properties were less likely to be accepted           (Leslie et al., 2011).
  than the neutral control properties. Experiment 3 showed by               The present research set out to examine the factors affecting
  contrast that gender-specific properties are more acceptable              the acceptability of minority characteristic generic
  when they relate to reproduction than to appearance-based                 statements relating to gender. All of the items in Leslie et
  gender differences. It is argued that reproductive properties
                                                                            al.’s set of minority characteristics used properties that were
  are more easily interpreted as referring to a kind rather than to
  the set of individual members.                                            just true of one gender of an animal kind. For example there
                                                                            were sentences such as “lions have manes” or “insects lay
  Keywords: generics, gender-specific, concepts                             eggs”. Our research question was whether the acceptability
                                                                            of such sentences (even in universally quantified form) is
                         Introduction                                       the result of their association with gender. For example,
When we describe the nature of the world, we typically use                  there may be some implicit pragmatic understanding that a
“generic” sentences. These are unquantified statements                      gender modifier (male or female) is intended by the speaker.
making general statements whose truth is resistant to                       When someone asserts “sheep give milk”, it could be argued
counterexamples (Carlson & Pelletier, 1995). Recent                         that the hearer assumes that the speaker intends “sheep” to
interest in generics has focused, for example, on the way in                refer only to the females. Accordingly in Experiments 1 and
which children understand gender-based statements                           2 (which are close replications) we compared two
(Cimpian & Markman, 2011) and how generic statements                        conditions, one in which a generic property was true of just
serve to reinforce stereotypes and belief in the essential                  one gender of a fictitious animal, and one in which it was
nature of social categories (Leslie, 2014).                                 true of just one of two subtypes, unrelated to gender. We
The logic of generic sentences and their truth evaluation has               predicted that the gender-related generics would be more
proven to be a highly complex issue, and is still the subject               likely to be accepted as true than the gender-neutral
of much debate (Greenberg, 2003; Leslie, 2014;                              generics.
Liebersman, 2011). Our aim in the present paper is to
explore one particular empirical question concerning                                               Experiment 1
statements that describe “minority characteristics” true of                 The first experiment was designed to test whether minority
less than 50% of the members of a kind. For example, the                    characteristics would be accepted as true more readily if
sentences “Ducks lay eggs” and “Mosquitoes carry malaria”                   they relate to one particular gender rather than to a non-
are typical generics. These sentences strike us as clearly                  gender based variety within a species. We hypothesised that
true, even if we realize that only adult female ducks lay eggs              people interpret the generic “ducks lay eggs” as applying to
and only a small proportion of mosquitoes carry malaria.                    a subset of the kind, in particular just to the females. Hence
Leslie, Khemlani, and Glucksberg (2011) established that                    they would accept a minority characteristic generic sentence
generic statements about “minority characteristics” can still               when it was true of females, but not males, but would reject
be considered true when they are given universal                            it if it was true of just one half of a species, but regardless of
quantification, as in the sentence “All ducks lay eggs”,                    gender.
which is only true of a minority of ducks. It is as though


                                                                      158
Method                                                                  3) It lives in forests (True)
Participants. Fifty students at “Kore University” of Enna               4) It grows spots on its wings in spring (Generic-female)
(Italy), participated voluntarily, 25 in each group.                    5) It has crest on its head (Generic-male)
                                                                        6) It eats nuts and seeds (False)
                                                                        7) It has a yellow tail (False)
                                                                        8) It eats small fishes (True)
                                                                        9) It has a sharp beak (Generic-male)
                                                                        10) It has a cooing call (Generic-female)

                                                                        The true sentences matched information given about the
                                                                        whole species, while the generic sentences were only true of
                                                                        one of the pictured creatures. Two booklets were created,
                                                                        one for each Condition. The order of the stories within the
                                                                        booklets was randomized. The task was translated into
                                                                        Italian by the first author (e.g. 8) Si nutre di piccoli pesci).
Figure 1: Rattle Bird, Male (or Type A) on the left and                 Design and Procedure. Participants were randomly divided
Female (or Type B) on the right, in Experiments 1 & 2.
                                                                        into 2 groups, each receiving one of the 2 booklets (either
                                                                        the gender or the neutral) with the four sets of stories. The
Materials. Each booklet contained four sets of illustrated              first page of each booklet contained a cover sheet with the
descriptions of four fictional dimorphic species of creatures           instructions “This experiment is simple and short. You will
(Tabbie Toad, Rattle Bird, Crabby Beatle, Cranky Fish). In              be shown a couple of pictures of fictional creatures, and a
each story, a picture and description was given of two                  text that describes them. Then you will be asked to say
different types, and of the species in general, which was               whether a number of sentences are true or false for the
referred to with a Definite Singular phrase. In the Gender              species, based on the information you have been given”.
group, the two types were labeled as male and female, while             Participants circled one of 2 response options (true or false),
in the Neutral group they were labeled as two sub-varieties             printed to the right of each sentence.
with both male and female members.
For example, the gender-based story for the Rattle Bird was
as follows (but in Italian):

   The Rattle Bird comes in two forms corresponding to the
male and the female of the species. This is the male Rattle
Bird (left). This is the female Rattle Bird (right). In spring,
the female Rattle Bird grows spots on its wings.
[Accompanying picture]. These Rattle Birds are found in
France. The male has a sharp beak, and a crest on its head,
whereas the female doesn’t have either. The female has a
coo-ing call, but the male is silent. The Rattle Bird lives in
forests and dense woodland and is related to the dove; it
only eats worms, beetles and small fishes that can be found
in small lakes and rivers.
                                                                        Figure 2: Distribution of responses across conditions in
The gender-neutral version of the story was similar but                 Experiment 1
began:
                                                                        Results and discussion. Responses to True and False
The Rattle Bird comes in two closely related forms with                 statements were strongly positive and negative as predicted.
some minor differences. Both male and the female of the                 Interest centred on the acceptance of the generic test
species can have either appearance, and the two forms,                  statements in each condition. Each participant saw four
which are equally common, interbreed freely. This is the                species and judged four generic statements about each,
brown form of the Rattle Bird (left). This is the yellow form           giving a total possible number of “true” judgments of 16.
of the Rattle Bird (right)                                              Figure 1 shows the distribution of number of true judgments
                                                                        to generics by condition (gender or neutral). The first point
Each text was followed by 9 sentences: 4 generic (2 each for            to note is that the distribution is non-normal. Both
male and for female in the gender condition), 3 true and 3              conditions showed considerable variation between
false. For instance, for the noun “Rattle Bird” the following           individuals, with 13 of the 25 participants in the Gender
10 sentences were constructed:                                          condition choosing to accept either all (6) or none (7) of the
1) It is only found in Asia (False)                                     statements. The Neutral condition showed a more uniform
2) It is related to the dove (True)                                     distribution, with a slightly greater preponderance of



                                                                  159
participants accepting the majority of the generics (16 out of         happier to allow a generic to be true of only one kind of
25, compared to 14 out of 25 for the gender condition).                creature when it was NOT associated with a male/female
Overall, 52% of generics in the Gender condition were                  difference.
considered true, while 66% of the neutral generics were
estimated true. Thus, the amount of agreement with the
generic statements was in fact greater for the neutral stories
than for the gender based stories. Because of the
distributions, a median-split chi-square test was used to test
for differences in frequencies across conditions, and showed
no significant difference (χ2 = 0.3, p >,5).
The results therefore leant no support to our hypothesis that
minority characteristics would be better supported when
they were specifically related to one gender. To test the
robustness of this result we decided to replicate the study
while making one change to the materials. In Experiment 1
we used the Definite Singular form for describing the kinds
and an anaphoric singular sentence to express the generic
statements. Previous research (e.g. Khemlani et al., 2007;             Figure 3: Distribution of responses in Experiment 2
2012; Leslie et al., 2011) used bare plurals in their
experiments (i.e. ducks lay eggs) and found high rates of              Nevertheless, changing the noun from singular into bare
acceptance (e.g. 89% of gender-based minority                          plural, and repeating the noun in the sentences also had an
characteristics were accepted as true in Khemlani et al,               apparent impact on the results. While acceptability was
2007). We therefore sought to replicate the results of                 much the same in the neutral case, acceptability of a gender-
Experiment 1 with the same materials and design, but                   specific characteristic was much lower with the bare plural
changing the definite singular phrase (The Rattle Bird) to             noun placed at the head of each sentence. It is possible that
the bare plural form (Rattle Birds).                                   the definite singular form “The Rattle Bird as a species”
In addition, to be sure that the scope of the sentences was            encourages interpretation of the sentences as referring to the
understood, we repeated the bare plural noun phrase at the             relevant gender only, so making them more acceptable (but
start of each sentence (e.g. Rattle birds are only found in            still no more acceptable that a gender-neutral distinction).
Asia).                                                                 On the other hand the bare plural “Rattle Birds” clearly
                                                                       refers to the whole set of individuals, and so the fact that the
                      Experiment 2                                     characteristic does not apply to one of the genders may be
                                                                       more evident. Further research is needed to explore the basis
In Experiment 2 we aimed to replicate the first experiment             of this effect.
with some changes. In order to emphasize the generic nature
of the sentences we used a bare plural form in both the story                                Experiment 3
and the sentences in place of the singular definite form “The          It is striking that in spite of a high rate of acceptance of
Rattle Bird” and anaphoric pronoun “it lives in forests”.              gender-based minority characteristics in previous research
Otherwise the procedure was unchanged.                                 (e.g. Khemlani et al., 2007), our results were far less
                                                                       positive. One possible reason may be the fictional creatures
Method                                                                 that we have used. One aim of Experiment 3 was therefore
Participants. A further 50 students at “Kore University” of            to compare fictional cases with real-life examples, to see
Enna (Italy), participated without any reward.                         whether the use of fictional cases is valid. The second aim
Material. The materials were the same as in Experiment 1               was to test an alternative hypothesis about when gender-
save for the changes described above.                                  based minority characteristics would be acceptable.
Design and Procedure. The design and procedure were the                Gender-based generics in previous research have sometimes
same as in Experiment 1.                                               used reproductive properties (“lays eggs”, “suckles its
Results and Discussion. As in Experiment 1 we counted                  young”) and sometimes differential appearance (“has a
the number (out of 16) of generics that were judged as true            mane”, “is red”). By contrast, all the sentences used in
by each participant. The distributions for each condition are          Experiments 1 and 2 were about appearance only. We
shown in Figure 3. This time, agreement with the generic               hypothesized that a key factor in accepting the truth of
statements was clearly greater for the neutral stories (58%)           gender-specific minority characteristics may relate to
than for the gender based stories (12%).                               reproduction per se, rather than to other gender related
This time the difference between the generalization of                 features. We therefore constructed gender stories
generics in the neutral and the gender condition was much              differentiating between features of physical appearance and
greater and significant (χ2 = 13.3, p < .001 on a median               reproduction. We then expected a stronger True response for
test). Thus, contrary to our prediction, people were much


                                                                 160
the generics about reproduction than for the generics about             first, because of a contrast with the less convincing fictional
appearance.                                                             cases which they followed.
  The Experiment therefore had two factors, fictional versus
real-life creatures and reproductive versus appearance
gender-based properties. We predicted that acceptance
would be stronger for real-life than for fictional cases, but
that the difference between reproductive and appearance
features would be evident in both kinds of case.

Method
Participants. A further 50 students at “Kore University”
of Enna (Italy), participated voluntarily.
Materials. Each booklet contained four sets of descriptions
with pictures: two based on real creatures (lions and deer)
and two on fictional dimorphic creatures (Tabbies and
Rattles). Each story was followed by 6 sentences: 2 true, 2
false, 1 generic on physical appearance (i.e. lions have
manes), and 1 generic on reproduction (i.e. lions give live
birth to their young). The order of the stories within the
booklets was randomized. The form of the sentences was a
bare plural as in Experiment 2.
Design and Procedure. Participants were randomly divided
into 2 groups, one group first saw the two stories based on
real animals and then the two fictional creatures, while the
other group saw the stories in the opposite order. Thus, the            Figure 5. True Responses by condition In Experiment 3.
condition of order of appearance was between subjects and               Error bars show Standard Error.
the type of creature (real or fictional) and type of generic
(reproduction or appearance) was within. The first page of              These results supported our prediction that reproduction is
each booklet contained a cover sheet with instructions.                 an exceptional case that encourages generics because the
Participants circled one of 2 response options (true or false),         predicate isn’t so much “false” of the males, as that it just
printed to the right of each sentence.                                  doesn’t sensibly apply. On the other hand appearance
                                                                        features are quite free to be true of either gender, and so are
                                                                        less likely to be accepted as true.
                                                                        Real cases were better liked than the fictional ones, but both
                                                                        showed the same effect. This result validates our use of
                                                                        fictional examples. While participants found them less
                                                                        convincing overall, the same preference for reproductive
                                                                        characteristics was shown with both types of material.

                                                                        General discussion
                                                                        Our three experiments are an initial exploration of why and
                                                                        when people are willing to accept minority characteristics as
Figure 4: Male and Female Lions in Experiment 3                         generically true. Previous research (Khemlani et al., 2007)
                                                                        has shown that people accept the truth of sentences which
Results and Discussion. The data were submitted to                      are only true of a minority of a class. However all the
ANOVA with within-subjects factors of Real vs Fictional                 sentences of this kind that they studied related to gender-
and Reproduction vs Appearance. There were significant                  specific features such as “lions have manes” or “ducks lay
main effects of Reproduction vs. Appearance (F(1,49) =                  eggs”. Our results provide some further understanding of
18.02, p < .001) and of Fictional vs. Real (F(1,49) = 8.73, p           these interesting cases. First, in Experiments 1 and 2, we
< .005). There was no interaction, F<1, (see Figure 5).                 showed that, surprisingly, people are less willing to accept
We found also a significant effect of the order of appearance           that a minority characteristic is true of a class when it is
of the two conditions, which however did not interact with              linked to gender. In Experiment 2, 58% of generics were
the other factors. There was a contrast effect. When the                accepted when they were true of an arbitrary subset of the
fictional cases were seen first, they received higher ratings           class, but only 12% were accepted when they were true of
generally than when seen second, following the more                     only one specific gender.
convincing real cases. By contrast when the real cases were                Experiment 3 explored a further question about minority
seen second they received higher ratings than when seen                 characteristics, namely whether gender based features that



                                                                  161
relate to reproduction may be more acceptable than those               Khemlani, S., Leslie, S.J. & Glucksberg, S. (2012).
that refer to appearance. In Leslie et al.’s data, the                   Inferences about Members of Kinds: The Generics
overgeneralisation to universally quantified sentences (e.g.             Hypothesis. Language and Cognitive Processes, 27, 887-
“All ducks lay eggs”) was more convincing with                           900
reproductive features than with appearance (e.g. “All                  Khemlani, S., Leslie, S., Glucksberg, S., & Fernandez, P.R.
kangaroos have pouches”), possibly because of the                        (2007). Do Ducks Lay Eggs? How People Interpret
ignorance of some participants. To avoid problems of                     Generic Assertions. Proceedings of the 29th Annual
ignorance, we provided our participants with the relevant                Cognitive Science Society. Nashville, TN: Cognitive
information in a short text, and then tested the acceptability           Science Society.
of the generics. We found that indeed reproductive features            Leslie, S. (2014). Carving up the social world with generics.
were generally better accepted (76% of judgments in the                  Oxford Studies in Experimental Philosophy, 1, 208-232.
case of real creatures) than appearance features (51%).                Leslie, S. (2015). Generics Oversimplified. Nous, 49, 28-54.
Leslie (2015) discusses a suggestion by Liebesman (2011)               Leslie, S., Khemlani, S., & Glucksberg, S. (2011). All ducks
to the effect that generics are statements not about                     lay eggs: The generic overgeneralization effect. Journal
individuals (singular or plural) but about kinds. Similarly              of Memory and Language, 65, 15-31.
Hampton (2012a; 2012b) proposes that generics are                      Liebesman, D. (2011). Simple Generics. Nous, 45, 409–442.
considered true when they include information that is a part
of the intensional prototype that represents the kind. That
could explain why very rare but striking properties are also
commonly accepted as true (e.g. sharks attack bathers).
They are a part of our knowledge base about the kind,
because of the need to take suitable precautions when
swimming near sharks, and the spectacularly dire
consequences of failing to do so. Given this framework, it is
possible that reproductive features are more easily attributed
to the kind than are gender-based appearance features.
Ducks laying eggs is relevant to both male and female
ducks, simply because they all, as individuals, began life
this way. On the other hand lions having manes is quite
specific to the males.
Another explanation for our result in Experiment 3 relates to
a hypothesis put forward by Andrei Cimpian (Cimpian &
Markman, 2011) that generics are more likely to be
acceptable when they reflect essential or deep causal
properties of a kind. Reproductive features are a part of a
network of strongly related properties of a kind, embedded
in theories of sexual reproduction and the rearing of
offspring. They would therefore be more likely to find
acceptance as generics than gender-differentiating
appearance features.


                       References
Carlson, G. N., & Pelletier, F. J. (1995). The generic book.
  Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press.
Cimpian, A., & Markman, E.M. (2011). The
  Generic/Nongeneric distinction influences how children
  interpret new information about social others. Child
  Development, 82, 471-492.
Greenberg, Y., (2003). Manifestations of Genericity.
  Routledge. New York.
Hampton, J. A. (2012a). Generics as reflecting conceptual
  knowledge. Recherches Linguistiques de Vincennes, 41,
  pp. 9-24.
Hampton, J. A. (2012b). Thinking intuitively: The rich (and
  at time illogical) world of concepts. Psychological
  Sciences, 21, 398-402.



                                                                 162