=Paper=
{{Paper
|id=Vol-1419/paper0036
|storemode=property
|title=An Interest and Belief-Based Model of Explicit Communication
|pdfUrl=https://ceur-ws.org/Vol-1419/paper0036.pdf
|volume=Vol-1419
|dblpUrl=https://dblp.org/rec/conf/eapcogsci/Cruciani15
}}
==An Interest and Belief-Based Model of Explicit Communication==
An interest and belief-based model of explicit communication Marco Cruciani (cruciani@disi.unitn.it) Dept. of Information Engineering and Computer Science University of Trento, Italy Abstract Corazza and Dokic, 2012; Stojnic and Lepore, 2013; Devit, 2013; Stalnaker, 2014;). There is also lively debate within The paper outlines an inferential model of explicit the pragmatics, which contains and extends the previous communication. The first section presents the main notions issues, for instance: mind-reading, ad hoc concepts involved in the model, that is, the speaker’s intended meaning construction, mutual adjustment and backward/forward and addressee’s intended meaning. The first notion is centred on the speaker’s interest in situation: a speaker intends the inference, impliciture vs. explicature, inferential vs. meaning of an utterance on the basis of a partial order of associative method, radical vs. moderate contextualism, etc. preferences with respect to a set of contextually plausible (Sperber & Wilson, 1986, 2002; Recanati, 2007, 2010, meanings. The second notion is centred on the addressee’s 2012; Carston, 2007, 2009; Wilson, & Carston, 2007; Hall, communicative inference, which is based on the addressee’s 2009, 2014; Bach, 2010; Mazzone, 2011; Mazzarella 2011; belief about the speaker’s interest and on the linguistic form Wilson & Sperber 2012; Carston & Hall, 2012; Belleri, of a sentence. In the following sections, the paper presents the 2013, 2014). phenomenon of semantic underdeterminacy, introduces the However, for the purpose of the paper, it is relevant the preferences partial order, and the communicative inferences. debate concerning the nature of the “primary” pragmatic The paper takes the notion of interest from cognitive social theory, the notion of meaning from semantics, the notion of processes, that are, the processes that contribute to the explicit meaning from pragmatics, and uses the notion of recovery of the explicit meaning of a sentence1. Relevance communicative inference for explicit meaning in partial Theory has proposed a unified inferential account of accordance with Relevant Theory. Finally, the paper discusses primary (i.e. explicatures) and secondary (i.e. implicatures) some examples taken from the pragmatist literature. pragmatic processes. Recanati conceives of this distinction as correlating with two different on-line processing systems: Keywords: states of affairs; truth-conditions; semantic for primary processes, there is a low-level associative underdeterminacy; speaker’s interest; speaker’s intended system, which is responsible for the derivation of ‘what is meaning; addressee’s belief; inference; addressee’s intended said’ (explicit meaning), and, for secondary processes, there meaning; shared intended meaning; explicit communication. is a genuinely inferential system, which recovers ‘what is implicated’.2 In short, the current debate is animated by numerous questions. For example: what is the role of truth- Introduction conditions in determination of the explicit meaning? What type of non-linguistic knowledge is necessary? In what does Communication is a phenomenon which pervades all the contribution of non-linguistic knowledge consist? How human activity. It is studied by various disciplines from can such knowledge be obtained? And how is it used? Is it different theoretical perspectives. Whatever the perspective the premise of a non-demonstrative inference, or does it taken, however, studying communication involves activate a frame that associates concepts? Are the primary investigation of a complex phenomenon which by its nature processes conscious or unconscious? Etc. requires dialogue among disciplines. Some important theories in philosophy, linguistics and cognitive science Speaker’s intended meaning and addressee’s share the idea that full understanding of communication intended meaning requires understanding the role of the non-linguistic knowledge tied to the situation in which a sentence is The paper presents a model of explicit communication, uttered, for instance: Récanati’s truth-conditional where the notion of shared intended meaning is based on the pragmatics, Bach’s 'quasi-contextualism', and the speaker’s preference for a state of affairs to which a communicative-inferential model developed by Sperber and sentence refers, and on the addressee’s communicative Wilson). Pragmatists (i.e. contextualists and relevant 1 theorists) and semanticists (i.e. minimalists, indexicalists) Cf. Carston (2002) on the notion of explicature in Relevant have given rise to numerous standpoints about different Theory; Récanati (2001) on ‘what is said’ in Truth-conditional aspects related to the context-dependence of meaning (e.g. Pragmatics; Bach (2010) on impliciture in linguistics. 2 indexicality, reference assignment, literal meaning, semantic According to Recanati’s framework, primary pragmatic processes are governed by a dynamics of accessibility, constrained underdeterminacy, semantics/pragmatics distinction, what is by semantic associations and world-knowledge structures (i.e. said/what is implicated distinction, unarticulated ‘schemata’) (Récanati, 2010). According to Relevant theory’s constituents, pragmatic intrusion, etc.) (Stanley, 2000; framework, utterances come with a presumption of their own Récanati, 2004a; Bianchi, 2004; Bach 2004; Szabó, 2005; optimal relevance, which guides the derivation of explicatures, Cappelen, 2007; Carston, 2008; Gaucker, 2012; Borg, 2012; contextual assumptions and implicatures (Wilson and Sperber, 2012). 240 inference, which involves the addressee’s belief about the the truth-conditions of a sentence, we have speaker’s interest of speaker in the specific communicative situation. intended meaning. The paper develops previous works of the author. The two Addressee’s intended meaning The addressee’s intended main thesis are in the following: 1) given a set of meaning is obtained via a communicative inference (Fig. 2). contextually plausible interpretations of a sentence, the The premise P1 consists of a sentence and the semantic speaker’s intended meaning is determined by the speaker’s conventions associate to its linguistic form (that is, some situational interests (Cruciani, 2010), and 2) the addressee’s semantically plausible meanings). The premise P2 consists intended meaning is inferred by addressee on the basis of of the addressee’s belief about the speaker’s interest, more his/her belief about the speaker’s interest (Cruciani, 2011)3. specifically about a partial ordering of speaker’s Communication is successful when the intended speaker’s preferences. meaning and addressee’s speaker meaning are shared, that is, when the addressee’s inference is based on a true belief speaker’s intended meaning about speaker’s interest in situation. The paper takes the notion of interest from cognitive social theory, that is, an interest is viewed as a state of affairs preferred by a speaker because it implies the [state of affairs preferred]goal conditions of possibility of his/her goal (this is a modified notion originally proposed by Conte Castelfranchi, 1995). Also, the paper takes the notion of meaning from analytic [state of aff. 1 ≥ state of aff. 2 ≡ state of aff. n] interest philosophy of language (semantics), that is, the sentence possibility-cond. meaning identifies with the truth-conditions of sentence, and the meaning of an expression identifies with its contribution to the truth value of the sentence in which it appears (Tarski, 1944). [interpret.1 interpret. 2 interpret. n] context Speaker’s intended meaning. The notion of speaker’s truth-cond. 1 truth-cond. 2 truth-cond. n intended meaning of declarative sentences is founded on the relation between the states of affairs in which a sentence is true and the speaker’s preferences ordering in regard to the states of affairs in which the sentence is true. A sentence can be true with respect to different sets of truth-conditions, sentence which correspond to different states of affairs. The state of Figure 1 affairs preferred by a speaker because it implies his/her goal provides the truth-conditions which determine the speaker’s Fig.1 – The schema illustrates the notion of speaker’s intended meaning in the specific situation of use. From this intended meaning as it is conceived here. perspective, the determination of speaker’s intended meaning is viewed as a selection of a state of affairs which P1 = Sentence (linguistic form and semantic conventions). makes a sentence true (via truth conditions) and satisfies the speaker’s interest in situation. Hence, the process of determining speaker’s intended meaning can be explained in C = Addressee’s intended meaning (truth-cond. level). terms of preferences ordering. The schema in Figure 1 illustrates the notion of speaker’s intended meaning as it is conceived here.4 At the bottom of P2 = Belief (speaker’s interest). the schema is a sentence which, given a context of use, has some plausible interpretations. Each interpretation refers to Fig. 2 – The schema illustrates the notion of addressee’s a state of affairs which makes the sentence true: that is, it intended meaning as it is conceived here. refers to specific truth-conditions. The correspondence between the state of affairs preferred by the speaker and one of the states of affairs which make the sentence true An important aspect is that the validity of this kind of determines the speaker’s intended meaning. In other words, inference (i.e. abduction) does not depend on logical when the possibility-conditions of the goal’s speaker match relation between premises (as for instance the case of indexical expressions, where the relation variable-content is logical). More precisely, it is not necessary that the non- 3 linguistic knowledge used in P2 is accessible, that is These notions are developed by the analysis of meaning constrained, by the linguistic form of sentence. In other negotiation processes in linguistic controversies provoked by ambiguous clauses in contracts (Cruciani 2009a, 2012). words, P2 is composed of inarticulated constituents (cf. 4 The line of interest in Figure 1 represents a partial order of Récanati. 2002). preferences, where “≥” stands for the preference relation “at least In the following, the paper presents the phenomenon of good as”, and “≡”stands for the preference relation “equal in value semantic underdeterminacy; it introduces the speaker’s to”, as specified in the following of the paper. 241 preferences; it presents the communicative inferences for form of ice on the surface and if there is water in the form of explicit meaning; and in the last section it argues in favour gas in the atmosphere. The two truth conditions correspond of the role of the speaker’s interest and beliefs’ addressee in to different states of affairs: the communicative inferences. a. “There is ice on the surface of Pluto”; Semantic underdeterminacy in semantics and pragmatics b. “There is water vapour in the atmosphere of Pluto”. This section illustrates the phenomenon of semantic Hence, (1) can refer to both states of affairs. This is the case underdeterminacy, and outlines some differences between if we consider semantic conventions, but also if we consider semantics and pragmatics. the text of the sentence in which the word “water” appears Semantic underdeterminacy occurs when the conventional and we use encyclopaedic knowledge (e.g. physical states of meaning of a sentence used by a speaker in a specific water). situation, coded by semantic conventions, underdetermines Hence, if pragmatic processes, based on non-linguistic the proposition explicitly expressed by the utterance (Travis, contextual information, are not sufficient to determine a 1975; Searle, 1979). The question is whether conventional unique set of truth-conditions (proposition), then, in order to meaning (obtained by linguistic conventions and rules) is determine the explicit level of communication, we can take sufficient to provide truth-conditions or whether other items into account the speaker’s preferences for the states of are required as well. In other words, is it sufficient to know affairs which make a sentence true. semantic conventions and linguistic rules or do we need to know elements of the specific situation of use? Partial ordering of state of affairs On a semantics view, conventional meaning and a small This section introduces the notion of preference for a state number of contextual parameters are sufficient to determine of affairs based on the comparative notions: “better than” the truth-conditions of a sentence (cf. Stanley, 2000; (>), “equal in value to” (≡) and “at least good as” (≥) taken Cappelen and Lepore, 2005). On a pragmatics view, from decision theory. Using this language, it is possible to conventional meaning is not sufficient to determine a unique express the preferences of agents for states of affairs. For set of truth-conditions (in pragmatics, semantic instance, on writing: [(sa1)>(sa2)]Ag, we assert that an agent underdeterminacy is considered pervasive of all language). prefers the state of affairs 1 rather than the state of affairs 2 Hence, we need information on the context of use to (see Fig. 1).5 complete the conventional meaning and to determine the Decisions theorists assume that an agent rationally truth-conditions. This information consists of shared chooses an option if the set of options realizes certain knowledge (encyclopaedic and local), the discourse or properties: ordering, continuity, independence (Myerson, sentence in which an expression is used, and elements of the 1991). For the purposes of the paper, it is sufficient to physical surroundings (cf. Récanati, 2004; Stalnaker, 2014). consider the property of ordering, which concerns Specifically, the paper deals with the problem of intended completeness and transitivity. meaning when a number of interpretations are all plausible Completeness for weak preference is defined as follows6: in the same combination of contexts, and not with the problem of whether there is a need for non-linguistic the relation ≥ is complete if and only if for any information to fix a unique set of truth conditions, there is a elements a and b of its domain, either a ≥ b or b ≥ a. need. Transitivity for weak preference is defined as follows: The example in the following can shed light on this point. The issue is the following: the conventional meaning of a the relation ≥ is transitive if and only if it holds for sentence, even without indexical expressions, and structural all elements a, b and c of its domain, so that if a ≥ b and lexical ambiguity, actually underdetermines the and b ≥ c, then a ≥ c. proposition expressed by the sentence. And even with the additional pragmatic contribution of relevant contextual These properties ensure that an agent is able to compare information, it is not always possible to fix a unique some options coherently with his/her own interest. proposition. The sentence is as follows: However, it is possible that an agent is not always able to compare all options clearly, but this does not prevent (1) “There is water on Pluto”. him/her from choosing coherently with his/her own interest. Hence, in order to consider an agent’s choice coherent with I do not know whether there is water on Pluto, but I his/her interest, it is sufficient that s/he is able to determine understand the sentence because I am able to imagine the ways in which there might be water on Pluto: for example, in the form of ice on the planet’s surface or in the form of 5 An agent’s preference can be also expressed via utility gas in its atmosphere. Consequently, sentence (1) can have function. For a set of options S, a utility function f maps each at least two interpretations (two different sets of truth- option onto R. The utility function gives rise to a preference conditions), that is, it can be true both if there is water in the relation “>” on S. For instance, (sa1)>(sa2) if only if f(sa1)>f(sa2). 6 Analogously we can define the relations “>” and “≡”. 242 the best state of affairs among others without necessarily high humidity alongside rivers (encyclopedic knowledge), ordering the other states of affairs. to determine the ways in which there is water on the bank. Knowing the partial ordering is a condition required by The two possible inferences are as follows: the speaker and the addressee because communication takes place successfully. P1: “The bank is wet” P2: Yesterday it rained alongside the river Inference of explicit meaning ----------------------------------------------------------------- This section illustrates the type of communicative inferences C: “There is water on grass, etc. alongside the river”. considered here, that is, non-demonstrative inferences7. They are structured as follows: P1: “The bank is wet” P2: Generally there is high humidity alongside rivers P1: Form and semantic conventions ----------------------------------------------------------------- P2: Contextual information C: “There is high humidity alongside the river”. -------------------------------------------- C: Explicit meaning The inferential processes involved in the determination of meaning of (2) are those of selection of ambiguity and Consider the following sentence: enrichment of truth-conditions. In (2) we can infer an interpretation of the word “bank” on the basis of contextual (2) “The bank is wet”. information directly perceived from the physical surroundings, and consequently we can infer an In (2) the meaning of the word “bank” is not determined, it interpretation of the word “wet” on the basis of local or can mean a financial institute or land alongside a river. In encyclopedic knowledge. cases of this kind, non-linguistic context provides I would stress that the validity of inference does not information with which to select a plausible interpretation. depend on logical relations between premises, that is, it is For example, on the one hand, if (2) is produced by a not necessary for communication that the non-linguistic speaker close to an angler who is about to fish, then “bank” information used in the second premise be made available plausibly refers to the land alongside a river and (2) by, or constrained to, linguistic form of expression. plausibly means that alongside the river there is high humidity; on the other hand, if the speaker is near to the Interest and belief in communicative inferences doors of a financial institute, then the word “bank” plausibly This section discusses the process of determining the refers to the institute and (2) plausibly means that the floor of the financial institute has just been washed. In both cases intended meaning of an utterance. It argues in favour of the the non-linguistic information is directly perceived from role of the speaker’s interests and the addressee’s belief physical surroundings (i.e. the angler and the financial concerning the speaker’s interests. The inference in question institute). Hence, the meaning of (2) is obtained through an has a premise which consists of information about the form inference composed of two premises: sentence (2) (semantic and the semantic conventions associated with the sentence conventions applied to the linguistic form) and the (which admits to several semantically plausible contextual information in which (2) is produced; the interpretations). The other premise consists of the content of conclusion consists of a unique proposition. The two the addressee’s belief about the speaker’s interest in the possible inferences are as follows: situation, i.e. it regards the state of affairs preferred by the speaker (insofar as it exhibits the possibility conditions of P1:“The bank is wet” his/her goal). The conclusion consists of a unique P2: Direct perception of the financial institute proposition, the one explicitly expressed by the speaker with ------------------------------------------------------------- the utterance. Or, as in the case that follows, it consists of a C:“The floor of the financial institute has just been washed”. part of the proposition that contributes, as the premise of another inference, to determination of the utterance’s overall P1: “The bank is wet” meaning. Consider the following sentence taken from the P2: Direct perception of the angler pragmatics literature (Carston, 2007). ------------------------------------------------------------- C: “There is high humidity alongside the river”. (3) “I’m going to the bank now to get some cash”. Consider (2) produced by a speaker close to angler about to At first glance, here the interpretative problem consists in fish: the word “wet” can refer to both high humidity and identifying a referent for the word “bank” (‘financial water on grass, rocks, etc. Here the form or the way in institution’ or ‘river side’). Let us base our interpretation on which water is on the bank is not determined. We need the approach of Récanati’s Truth-conditional pragmatics. In further information: for instance, yesterday it rained this case it would be plausible to assume that the referent alongside the river (local knowledge); or generally there is ‘financial institution’ is assigned to the word “bank” 7 because it is associated with the concept ‘cash’ triggered by See Wilson and Sperber (2012) on the communicative inferences the word “cash”, or because it is associated with the in Relevant Theory. 243 stereotypical representation ‘getting money from a bank’ (or with both). This association is made possible by the In interpretation of (3), the shared knowledge of the discourse (or linguistic) context, i.e. the part of the sentence speaker’s interest enables determination of the meaning of in which the expression “to get some cash” appears, and by the expression “to get some cash” (‘sell fish’) which then the shared encyclopaedic knowledge that, in general, money allows assign of the reference for the word “bank” (‘river is withdrawn from banks.8 But this is not necessarily the side’). Hence, the interest (via enrichment) has determined intended interpretation, even though it is the most (i) the contribution of the expression “to get some cash” to immediate one. the truth-conditions of the sentence, and accordingly (ii) the Consider the case in which (3) is uttered by an angler who is relevant linguistic context for disambiguation of “bank” in going fishing and who intends to sell the fish that he the specific situation. catches. In this case, the encyclopaedic knowledge that Finally, an important characterization of the money is withdrawn from banks is not relevant, but nor is communication model is as follows. If we believe that the local knowledge that the speaker is a ‘professional’ knowledge of the speaker’s interests is used in the premise fisherman able to disambiguate the word “bank” (because of the addressee’s inference, then we admit that the meta- also fishermen go to the bank). Instead, if we know the representational capacities have a role in explicit speaker’s interests – for example, that he intends to sell the communication (i.e. in the determination of propositional fish that he catches in order to earn money, or that he content). We therefore assume that, although this process intends to withdraw money in order to go shopping – then often is automatic, it is conscious. Hence, in principle, the we are able to identify the intended referent in both the addressee can at any time justify, with respect to (3), the former and the latter case. We are able to do so on the basis assignment of reference to the word “bank” or of the knowledge shared between speaker and addressee determination of modes in which “to get some cash.” about the speaker’s interest, and not on the basis of conceptual associations produced by the addressee. If this is Conclusion how matters stand, then it is plausible that the speaker’s The paper has outlined a model of explicit communication interests and goals render the communicative models more for declarative sentences. Its elements are: the meaning as flexible and generalizable, and therefore preferable to truth-conditions, inferential process, the speaker’s interest as ‘mechanistic’ models – or at least to more rigid ones based a state of affairs preferred by the speaker because it implies on conceptual frames and schemata activated by the his/her goal; the partial ordering of states of affairs; and the addressee and presumed shared assumptions. addressee’s belief about speaker’s interest. Its arguments Presented below is the scheme of the inferential process are: the communicative intentions that trigger the whereby the addressee determines the meaning of (3): information of the pragmatic context often are not sufficient to select the speaker’s intended meaning among some “I’m going to the bank1,2 now to get some cash”. contextually plausible meanings (pars destruens), and thus it is necessary to take into account the partial order of preferences to determine the speaker’s intended meaning I’m going to the bank1,2 now to get some cash [fishing and selling (pars consrtuens). Its related notions are: ‘what is said’, fish]”. which refers to the explicit level of communication and is based on truth-theoretic machinery which delivers truth- conditions (Récanati, 2010). Nevertheless, the model differs Speaker’s interest: from the Truth-conditional Pragmatics because it comprises ‘fishing and selling fish’. the communicative inferences also for explicit meaning, and “I’m going to the river side now to get some cash it considers very relevant the active role of addressee in fishing and selling fish”. communication, as the case of explicature in Relevant Theory (Wilson and Sperber, 2012).9 In summary, the speaker intends the meaning that maximizes his/her interest in situation, and the addressee Linguistic context: ‘to get some cash [fishing and selling fish]’. infers the meaning on the basis of his/her belief about the speaker’s partial order of preferences. When the addressee Figure 3 – Inferential steps in determination of the meaning has a true belief about the partial order of preferences, we of (3). have shared intended meaning, that is, a real 8 communication. Following the same interpretation procedure, if at the beginning of utterance (3) the word “bank” is understood by the addressee in Acknowledgements the sense of ‘river side’, because for some reason the latter concept Very special thanks to Sonia Guglielminetti. is more activated and available to the addressee than ‘financial institution’, it is likely that the word “cash” in the continuation of the sentence will trigger the concept ‘cash’, which is associated 9 with the concept of ‘financial institution’, thus aligning the Rècanati uses “ascertaining” rather than "determination" with communication with the speaker’s intentions (accessibility shift) regard to the role of addressee in the process of determination of (see Recanati 2004a; Carston 2007). meaning. 244 References Hall, A. (2009) Free enrichment and the nature of pragmatic constraints. UCL WPL 21: 93–123. Bach, K. (2004). Minding the gap. In C. Bianchi (Ed.), The pragmatics/semantics distinction. Stanford: Csli. Hall, A. (2014) ‘Free’ enrichment and the nature of Bach, K. (2010). Impliciture vs explicature: What’s the pragmatic constraints”. International Review of difference? In Romero E. & Soria B. (Eds.) Explicit Pragmatics 6(1): 1-28. communication: Robyn Carston’s pragmatics. NY: Levinson, S. (2000). Presumptive meanings. Cambridge (MA): MIT Press. Palgrave. Mazzarella, D. (2011). Accessibility and relevance. A fork Belleri, D. (2013). Meta-representation in utterance in the road. UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 23:1-10 comprehension. Journal of Pragmatics, 57: 158-69. Mazzone, M. (2011). Schemata and associative processes in Belleri, D. (2014). Semantic under-determinacy and pragmatics. Journal of Pragmatics 43 (8): 2148-59. communication. Basingstoke: Palgrave. Myerson, R.B. (1991). Game theory. Cambridge: Harvard Bianchi, C. (Ed.) (2004). The pragmatics/semantics University Press. distinction. Stanford: Csli. Récanati, F. (2001). What is said. Synthese, 128, 75-91. Borg, E. (2012). Pursuing Meaning. Oxford: OUP. Récanati, F (2002). Inarticulated constituents. Linguistic and Cappelen, H. (2007). Semantics and pragmatics: Some Philosophy, 25 (3): 299-345. central issues. In G. Preyer & G. Peter (Eds.) Context- Récanati, F. (2004a). Literal meaning. Cambridge, CUP. sensitivity and Semantic Minimalism. Oxford: OUP. Récanati, F. (2004b). ‘What is said’ and the Cappelen, H. & Lepore, E. (2005). Insensitive Semantics: A semantics/pragmatics distinction. In C. Bianchi (Ed.), The defense of Semantic Minimalism and Speech Act semantics/pragmatics distinction. Csli: Stanford. Pluralism. Oxford, Blackwell. Récanati, F. (2007). Reply to Carston. In Frapolli M. (Ed.) Carston, R. (2002). Linguistic meaning, communicated Saying, meaning, referring, Palgrave, NY, 49-54. meaning and cognitive pragmatics. Mind and Language, Récanati, F. (2010). Truth conditional pragmatics. 17, 1-2, 127-148. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. Carston, R. (2007). How many pragmatic systems are there? Récanati F. (2012) Contextualism: Some varieties. In In M. Frappolli (Ed.) Saying, meaning, referring. Cambridge Handbook of Pragmatics, Cambridge: CUP. Palgrave McMillan, New York, pp. 18-48. Searle, J. (1979). Expression and meaning. Cambridge: Carston R. (2008). Linguistic communication and the CUP. sem./prag. distinction. Synthese 165(3): 321-45. Sperber, D., Wilson, D. (1986). Relevance theory: Carston R. (2009). The explicit/implicit distinction in communication and cognition. Oxford: Blackwell. pragmatics and the limits of explicit communication. Sperber, D. & Wilson, D. (2002) Pragmatics, modularity International Review of Pragmatics 1, 35-62. and mind-reading. Mind & Language 17: 3-23. Carston R. & Hall A. (2012) Implicature and explicature. In Stalnaker, R. (2014) Context. Oxford: OUP. H-J. Schmid & D. Geeraerts (Eds.) Cognitive Pragmatics, Stanley, J. (2000). Context and logical form. Linguistics & Handbooks in Pragmatics. De Gruyter: Berlin, 7-84. Philosophy 25: 701-21. Conte, R., Castelfranchi, C. (1995). Cognitive and social Stojnic U. & Lepore E. (2013) What’s What is Said? In action. London: University College London. Penco C. & Domaneschi F. (Eds.) (2013) What is said Corazza E. & Dokic J. (2012) Situated minimalism vs free and what is not. CSLI, Stanford, 17-36. enrichment. Synthese 184 (2):179-98; Szabó Z. (Ed.) (2005) Semantics Vs. pragmatics. Oxford: Cruciani, M. (2009a). Cono del linguaggio, negoziazione OUP. degli interessi e significato inteso di clausole contrattuali Tarski, A. (1944). The semantic conception of truth and the ambigue. Sistemi Intelligenti, 21(3): 473-88. foundation of semantics. Philosophical and Cruciani, M. (2009b). Intended meaning and situational Phenomenological Research, 4, 341-56. interest. Proc. of the 31th Conference of the Cognitive Travis, Ch. (1975). Saying and understanding. Oxford: Science Society. Austin, (TX): Cognitive Science Society, Blackwell. pp. 2747-52. Wilson D. & Carston R. (2007) A unitary approach to Cruciani, M. (2010) On the notion of intended meaning. lexical pragmatics: Relevance, inference and ad hoc Proc. of the 32th Conference of the Cognitive Science concepts. In Burton-Roberts N. (Ed) Pragmatics, Society Austin: Cognitive Science Society, pp. 1028-33. Palgrave, NY, 230–60. Cruciani, M. (2011) Communicative inferences and context Wilson, D. & Sperber, D. (2004) Relevance Theory. In of interests. In M. Beigl et al. (Eds.) Lecture Notes in Horn L. & Ward G.(eds.) Handbook of Pragmatics, Artificial Intelligence 6967, Springer: Heidelberg, pp. 71- Blackwell, Oxford, 607–32. 81. Wilson, D. & Sperber, D. (2012). Meaning and relevance. Cruciani, M. (2012) Meaning in use and linguistic disputes. Cambridge: CUP. In Cognitive Systems, 7-3:247-260. Devit M. (2013). Is there a place for Truth-Conditional Pragmatics? Teorema 32 (2): 85-102. Gauker, C. (2012) Semantics and Pragmatics. In G. Russell & D. Graff Fara (Eds.) Routledge companion to the Philosophy of Language, Routledge. 245