=Paper= {{Paper |id=Vol-1845/paper1 |storemode=property |title=Varieties of Contexts |pdfUrl=https://ceur-ws.org/Vol-1845/paper1.pdf |volume=Vol-1845 |authors=Carlo Penco,Massimiliano Vignolo }} ==Varieties of Contexts== https://ceur-ws.org/Vol-1845/paper1.pdf
        CEUR Proceedings of the Workshop on Contexts in Philosophy - Paris, June, 20, 2017




                                Varieties of Contexts
                           Carlo Penco and Massimiliano Vignolo

                                    University of Genoa
                                      penco@unige.it
                                massimiliano.vignolo@unige.it


         Abstract. In this presentation we give a short reminder on the origin of the
         two main notions of context that are used in philosophy of language in order
         to draw attention to the main points of discussion common in the meeting on
         “Contexts in Philosophy”.


The use of Context in philosophy begins with Frege’s work: in his book Foundations
of Mathematics (1884: xxii) he gives the following maxim: “never to ask for the
meaning of a word in isolation, but only in the context of a sentence”. This claim is a
criticism of Locke who endorsed the Aristotelian view of meaning as an idea con-
nected with a lexical item (for Aristotle words are signs not of objects, but of the
movement of the mind and for Locke the meaning of a word is the idea connected
with the word). Frege thought that Locke’s mistake was to look for the meaning of a
word in isolation; but (i) for many words there are no corresponding ideas, and the
only way to understand or define the meaning of a word is to study how it works in
the context of a sentence; (ii) different people may connect different ideas with the
same words.
    But Frege was worried also for other aspects of the use of language: context de -
pendence and fiction. While in mathematics we work with expressions (e.g. numerals)
that always refer to the same objects (numbers) independently of the context, in ev-
eryday speech, the reference of expressions like “I”, “today”, “this”, “here” changes
depending on the context of utterance. Frege dedicated much of his last writings to
discuss this peculiarity of natural language remarking that

         “The mere wording, as it can be preserved in writing, is not the
         complete expression of the thought; the knowledge of certain
         conditions accompanying the utterance, which are used as
         means of expressing the thought, is needed for us to grasp the
         thought correctly. Pointing the finger, hand gestures, glances

                                                 1
        CEUR Proceedings of the Workshop on Contexts in Philosophy - Paris, June, 20, 2017


          may belong here too. The same utterance containing ‘I’ in the
          mouth of different men, will express different thoughts.” (Frege
          1918: 64; in Beaney 1997: 332).

Especially in poetry and fiction, but not only, there is another problem: in natural lan-
guage we may use expressions that do not refer to any existing object (e.g. "the
winged horse" etc.). Frege suggested that when we use a definite description we pre-
suppose the existence of the object defined by the description: “when we make an as-
sertion we give it for presupposed that the simple or composed proper name has a
meaning” (Frege 1892). But this is a shared agreement, which not always is followed
by speakers, when they use non-referring expressions.
    These three kinds of remarks are at the beginning of three different concepts of
context, two of which became the most relevant in contemporary philosophy: (1) Lin-
guistic context, (2) Context of utterance (3) Cognitive context. The three different
concepts of context represent the main divide among different – although connected –
logical, philosophical and technical enterprises. Besides the first notion of linguistic
context – that has been developed in different areas of linguistics and computer sci-
ences, especially in information retrieval – the notions of context of utterance and of
cognitive context became the most important ones in the philosophical debate. The
notion of context of utterance, together with the notion of circumstances of evalua-
tions, is central in Kaplan’s truth conditional semantics: with the work of Kaplan we
have a standard definition of the notion of what is said as ‘the content of a sentence in
a context’. Kaplan provided a shared terminology concerning content, context (of ut-
terance) and circumstance of evaluation together with a specification of the proper
role of the context of utterance:

          “The character of an expression is set by linguistic conventions
          and, in turn, determines the content of the expression in every con-
          text. Because character is what is set by linguistic conventions, it is
          natural to think of it as meaning in the sense of what is known by
          the competent language user. Just as it was conventional to repre-
          sent contents by functions from possible circumstances to exten-
          sions (Carnap’s intensions), so it is convenient to represent charac-
          ters by functions from possible contexts to contents. This gives the
          following picture:
          Character: Contexts => Contents
          Content: Circumstances => Extensions
          Or, in more familiar language,
          Meaning + Context => Intensions
          Intension + Possible World => Extensions



                                                 2
        CEUR Proceedings of the Workshop on Contexts in Philosophy - Paris, June, 20, 2017


          Indexicals have a context-sensitive character. It is characteristic of
          an indexical that its content varies with context. Nonindexicals
          have a fixed character. The same content is invoked in all contexts”
          (Kaplan 1989a: 505-506).

Following Kaplan’s framework, John Perry gives a classification of indexicals, to-
gether with the distinction between narrow and wide context:

          The narrow context consists of the constitutive facts about the utter-
          ance, which I will take to be the agent, time and position. These
          roles are filled with every utterance. The clearest case of an indexi-
          cal that relies only on the narrow context is ‘I’, whose designation
          depends on the agent and nothing else. The wider context consists of
          those facts, plus anything else that might be relevant, according to
          the workings of a particular indexical” (Perry 1998: 5-7).

The distinction between narrow context and wide context is partly relying on the idea
put forward by Lewis 1980 according to whom everything that can shift may belong
to the context. But if we begin to put in the context "everything that might be rele -
vant" we are widening the concept of context from a metaphysical view - that is the
objective elements of the context of utterance - towards something that includes also
cognitive aspects, such as beliefs and intentions.
    An alternative notion of “cognitive” context has been developed by Robert Stal-
naker, working on the idea of dialogue: in every dialogue there is a common ground
of beliefs and information that we give for granted. How to characterize this common
ground and how to understand the relations between this common ground and what is
said in the dialogue? Here Stalnaker uses the notion of presupposition as the proposi -
tion that must be taken for granted in order for an utterance to be appropriate. His idea
is to develop the basic intuition behind Grice's theory of speaker’s meaning according
to which when speakers mean things, they act with the expectation that their inten -
tions to communicate are mutually recognized:

          “This idea leads naturally to a notion of common ground – the mu-
          tually recognized shared information in a situation in which an act
          of trying to communicate takes place. A representation of the com-
          mon ground helps to clarify both the end of the communicative ac-
          tion by representing the possibilities among which the speaker in-
          tends to distinguish, and the means available to the speaker to distin-
          guish between them – the information that must be available in or-
          der that the act of uttering certain noises reasonably be taken as an


                                                 3
        CEUR Proceedings of the Workshop on Contexts in Philosophy - Paris, June, 20, 2017


          act of trying to get someone to acquire certain information.” (Stal-
          naker 2002: 704)

This new concept of context as common ground of presupposed beliefs brings about a
new notion of meaning as context change potential: the meaning of a sentence (typi-
cally an assertion) may change the context by simply adding content to the context, or
by challenging something accepted in the context or in other ways such as influencing
the direction of the subsequent conversation. Update Semantics is just one of the
many frameworks aiming at developing a formal semantics grounded on the idea of
meaning as context change potential; while these semantics represent an alternative to
truth theoretical semantics, they still keep some idea of truth conditions as character-
izing the result of what is said.
     In both frameworks, truth conditional semantics and update semantics, a problem
still rests unanswered: what is said? (see e.g. Domaneschi-Penco 2013) Shall we fol-
low the traditional idea held by Paul Grice for whom what is said is expressed by the
literal, conventional meaning of the expressions, after the resolution of ambiguity and
indexicality, or shall we define what is said as something that is enriched by contex-
tual features? And how should we define a notion or a model of context useful to an -
swer this question? In the papers collected in this volume some authors try to answer
these questions with reference to Kaplan’s framework and others to Stalnaker’s views.
     While Yang Hu tries to clarify a minimalist model that might be more coherent
with Kaplan’s framework, most papers try to challenge aspects of that framework: the
two strongest criticisms are by Aldo Frigerio, who claims that demonstratives are not
direct referential expressions, and Palle Leth, who criticises the centrality of inten-
tions in defining the meaning of context dependent expressions. Tamara Dobler gives
semantics a space beyond the limits imposed by Kaplan by appealing to the concept
of practical goal to help determining the truth conditions of sentences containing oc-
casion sensitive predicates. Claudia Picazo Jaque develops a similar critique showing
how to derive contents that are linked to specific occasions and at the same time con -
tents that are invariant across contexts. As to the other concept of context inspired by
Stalnaker’s views, Carpintero tries to enrich the idea of common ground with the idea
of commitments connected with different speech acts. Filippo Domaneschi and Si-
mona di Paola derive some relevant theoretical ideas from experimental data on Stal-
naker’s notion of accommodation, while Salvatore Pistoia Reda works on the concept
of existential presupposition for quantified sentences, claiming that background
knowledge of possible worlds have a central role in defining the acceptability of the
presupposition.
    Finally, Sandro Balletta and Augustin Vicente aim at inserting in truth conditional
semantics aspects of ontologically driven lexical components, while Ernesto Perini
Santos gives a general challenge to the use of formal models for generating or inter-
preting natural languages: we cannot ask formal models to perform the role of ex-

                                                 4
        CEUR Proceedings of the Workshop on Contexts in Philosophy - Paris, June, 20, 2017


plaining natural language and the reference of its expressions, but formal models
should be used to represent compositionality once the references of expressions have
been defined outside the formal model itself.
    We thank all members of the Scientific Committee1 that helped us to select the pa-
pers for this workshop and the North Western Philosophy Consortium for sponsoring
this meeting under the project of Graduate Conferences in Philosophy, supported by
Compagnia San Paolo, and devoted to put together PhD Students and experts in the
field. This project was also supported by the National Research Project PRIN
2015L3BC35 on “Indeterminacy Problem: Meaning, Knowledge and Action”. We
thank also Sandro Balletta for his help in preparing the CEUR proceedings.

References

   Domaneschi F., Penco C. (eds), 2013, What is Said and What is Not, CSLI Publica-
tions, Stanford.

  Frege G. 1918, “Der Gedanke. Eine Logische Untersuchung”, in Beiträge des
Deutsche Idealismus , 1 (58-77); Engl. Transl. in Beaney M. (1996) Frege, Duck-
worth, London.

    Kaplan, D. 1989, “Demonstratives”, in Themes from Kaplan , eds. Almog, J. Perry,
J. and Wettstein, H., 481-563, Oxford: Oxford University Press

  Lewis, D. 1980, “Index, Context, and Content”, in Philosophy and Grammar, eds.
Kanger, S., & Öhman, S., Dordrecht: Reidel. Also in, Papers in Philosophical Logic ,
Lewis, D., 21-44, Cambridge: Cambridge U. P.

   Perry, J. 1998, “Indexicals and Demonstratives”, in Bob Hale and Crispin Wright
(eds.), A Companion to Philosophy of Language, pp. 586–612. Oxford: Blackwell.

  Stalnaker, R. 2002, “Common Ground”, in Linguistics and Philosophy 25: 701-
721.




1
  The Program Committee, besides us, was composed by Anne Bezuidenhout, Emma Borg,
Claudia Caffi, Manuel Garcia Carpintero, Eros Corazza, Katarzyna Kijania-Placek, Kepa Ko-
rta, Eva Picardi, Stefano Predelli, Mark Textor, Ken Turner.

                                                 5