=Paper= {{Paper |id=Vol-2383/paper10 |storemode=property |title=Ascribing Exchange Value |pdfUrl=https://ceur-ws.org/Vol-2383/paper10.pdf |volume=Vol-2383 |authors=Birger Andersson,Paul Johannesson |dblpUrl=https://dblp.org/rec/conf/vmbo/AnderssonJ19 }} ==Ascribing Exchange Value== https://ceur-ws.org/Vol-2383/paper10.pdf
                    Ascribing Exchange Value

                     Birger Andersson and Paul Johannesson

    Department of Computer and Systems Sciences, Stockholm University, Sweden
                             {ba,pajo}@dsv.su.se



       Abstract. There exist several forms of the value of notion in the liter-
       ature, including use value, economic value, exchange value, and market
       value. In this paper, we discuss how exchange value is related to use
       value by proposing a definition that defines exchange value in terms of
       compensations of use values.


1    Introduction

This paper addresses value ascription, investigating how actors can measure and
ascribe value to objects. An example could be a taster who samples a glass of
wine, ascribes some value to it according to a value structure, and compares the
value with those of other samples. For some time, there has been research on the
development of ontologies for value ascription in an enterprise modelling setting
[4, 1]. One question in this research is whether the value ascribed is ascribed
to the object being evaluated, the evaluator, or the relationship between the
object and the evaluator. In [4] it was proposed that value is ascribed to the
relationship, which is modelled as a relator [4]. Another question concerns the
notion of context, i.e., the situation in which an object is used, and its relation
to value ascription.
     In [1] some questions were answered in the form of an ontology that included
the notion of context as a key component. A limitation of the work done in [1]
was that it only addressed use value. This limitation reduces the applicability
of the ontology in a value network setting, which is primarily concerned with
economic and exchange values.
     Within economics, several kinds of value have been investigated. One of these
is use value that concerns the value an actor receives in the use of an object.
Another kind of value is economic value, which has been defined as “the maximum
amount a consumer is willing to pay for an item“ [5]. Similarly, Gordijn and
Akkerman state that "... a rational actor is only willing to exchange an object,
Oout , if it obtains another object Oin in return. Moreover, it must assign to object
Oin in a higher economic value than to object Oout " [3]. A third kind of value is
market value, which has been defined as "the price an asset would fetch in the
marketplace" [6], thus depending on demand and supply. While economic value
is relative to a single actor, market value is relative to a market, i.e., a group of
actors. The term “exchange value” can be used to refer to either economic value
or market value.
     In this paper, we propose an extension of the work started in [1] for the
purpose of ascribing exchange value. The extension relies on the view on eco-
nomic/exchange value by Gordijn and Akkermann, [3], but we have changed the
perspective from the buyer to the seller, thereby considering not what someone
is prepared to maximally pay or sacrifice, but instead what someone requires
minimally to receive in compensation. Thereby, we are able to provide a concep-
tualization of exchange value that relies on use value as a basis.
     The paper is structured as follows. Section 2 offers an overview of the work in
[1], while Section 3 contains the extension to include exchange value, and Section
4 lists some open issues.


2   Value Protocol Ontology

An agent is an endurant that can carry out actions and have intentions. An agent
can play two different roles in a value ascription: it can be the one for whom a
value is ascribed to a value object, and it can be the one who makes the value
ascription. These two roles are modelled by the associations for and by in figure
1. An agent performs a value ascription by assessing how well the qualities and
dispositions of a value object fit the needs and wants of herself or some other
agent.
    A value object is an object to which an agent can ascribe value. As argued
in [4], in principle any object can be a value object, including physical objects,
mental states, events, and actions. But we will here only consider value objects
as substantials, meaning that a value object has identity and persists over time.
Typical examples of value objects are goods, services and social relationships
based on these, such as orders and invoices.
    Through a value ascription event, an agent ascribes a value to a value object.
This value depends on properties of the agent as well as circumstances around
the agent. In order to capture these, we introduce the notion of a value protocol,
which consists of three components: (1) A context frame consisting of a set of
contexts that specify in which circumstances a value object will be used; (2) A
value structure consisting of a set of value dimensions that specify which kinds
of value that are to be considered in a value ascription; and (3) A comparison
frame consisting of a set of value objects that provide a base-line for a value
ascription.
    Value depends on the context, or contexts, in which a value object is intended
to be used. For example, a sports car may offer much status when used in the
context of driving to work but much less status when used for driving on a
countryside vacation. Intuitively, a context is a state of affairs with a hole that
leaves some relationships under specified. When the hole is filled by a value
object, the result is a state of affairs. Thus, ascribing value to a value object in
a context means to evaluate a state of affairs. The class VO Value Ascription
represents value ascriptions that take into account a context frame, consisting
of a set of contexts.
    The value ascribed in a value ascription is a value quale. In the simplest
case, it is just a scalar, e.g., a utilitarian value could be described by a single
number. In more complex cases, a value quale belongs to a value structure that
is a multi-dimensional space. Value ascriptions are justified through an analysis
of the fits between value objects, contexts and the needs, preferences, and desires
of agents.
    It is not the case that value can be ascribed in an absolute sense. Instead,
value ascriptions are about comparing value objects along one or several value
dimensions. As a consequence, performing a value ascription requires that in ad-
vance some set of value objects to be valued and compared have been identified.
This can be addressed by introducing a comparison frame, i.e., a set of value
objects that provide a baseline for a value ascription. The choice of comparison
frame will typically have a significant effect on the value ascribed by a value
ascription. For example, the same computer may be ascribed a high value on
convenience when compared to a set of legacy computers but a low value when
compared to a set of up-to-date premium computers.

3   Extended Value Protocol Ontology




                     Fig. 1. An Ontology for Value Ascription


   In this paper, we propose an extension of the ontology to also accommodate
the notion of exchange value. As stated the extension relies on views proposed
in [3] and [2]. When discussing value exchanges, [3] states that the goal behind
the value exchange modelling construct is to "...model a legal transfer of value
objects." Furthermore, it is stated that ’"A value exchange may coincide with a
flow of a physical product or information if these are of value to a stakeholder "
and "... a value exchange expresses a change of ownership (as an economic result,
not a process outcome)...". We interpret those quotes to say that an economic
exchange is concerned with the transfers of rights. The transfer of rights expresses
the legality of coincidental transfers of objects on a non-legal level. From REA
[2], we note the pattern where a duality of value transfers (an exchange) fulfills
some reciprocity of economic commitments by economic agents.
    The action theory of exchange (ATE) is supportive of the view that an eco-
nomic exchange is a duality of transfers [7]. Citing an example from the paper,
exchange is formulated as "Julie transfers her bike to Paul and, in exchange,
Paul transfers his money to her ".
    As in REA an agent acts as a party in a contract. Parties in contracts are
always economic agents in the REA sense. The cardinality constraint is that a
contract is always related to two agents. This is a limitation as real-world con-
tracts often include more than two parties. This is, however, usually solved by
means of sub-contracts. A contract is made up of one or several clauses express-
ing the parties’ commitments. In other words, a contract contains promises that
the parties related to the contract commit to do something. A commitment may
concern the reservation of a value object. A reservation of a value object means
that it cannot be reserved in another commitment in the contract. The reserva-
tion indicates which value object the commitment is about. Each commitment
stands in a reciprocal relationship with another, i.e., the duties and privileges of
one party correspond to some duties and privileges of the other party. Commit-
ments are fulfilled by transfers of rights on the reserved value object from one
party (the rights holder) to the other. A pair of transfers stands in a duality rela-
tion with each other. That is, through the transfer of a right a party satisfies an
obligation to respect the other party’s claim thereby fulfilling a duty to honour
a privilege as the party has committed himself to. The duality relation implies
that the other party also satisfies his corresponding obligation. As stated, what
is transferred between the agents are rights (e.g. ownership or lease) on a value
object. Exchanges always concern transfers of rights. Note that we consider a
commitment to be a value object in itself. This means that a commitment (es-
sentially a promise) is an object that can, as any value object, be ascribed a
value. Furthermore, it may also be reserved as a value object in a contract and
the rights on it can be transferred. Based on the extended ontology, we can now
define exchange value as follows.


    An exchange value for a rights holder R regarding a value object VO
    is an acceptable use value of a compensating value object VO that R
    demands in order to enter a contract that includes a commitment to
    transfer rights on R’s VO as well as a commitment to transfer rights on
    a compensating value object C to R
In [1] the value protocol was introduced as a conceptual structure central for
value ascription. It was exemplified as a tabular structure with value objects in
the leftmost column and contexts in the other. For example, in Figure 2 there
is but one value object (Ford Focus) with three contexts (at work, on vacation,
in exchange). The third context, in exchange, represents the extension of the
ontology presented in this paper. A value in a cell in the table is a quale (see
Section 2). It is the value ascribed to a value object for its use in the context
indicated as a column header. For example, the value of a Ford Focus for use
in the context ’at work’ is here  i.e., on the value dimension ’fun’ the
value object has the value 9 (without going into detail on how to understand
the scale). The context ’in exchange’ represents the value of the value object




                         Fig. 2. Extended Value Protocol


as used in an exchange similarly to the other contexts. In the example table,
it is stated that in exchange the value of the value object is  but
what is the meaning of this value ascription? There are some alternatives: it
can mean that the exchange of the car in itself is rather pleasurable or it can
mean that getting rid of the car is pleasurable or it can mean that, similar to a
price tag, it is what the owner of the car expects in return for transferring the
ownership of the car to some other agent, which agrees with the above definition.
The extension of the ontology is able to reflect this latter view. The meaning of
a value ascription in an exchange context is the use value the owner of a value
object demands in order to enter an agreement resulting in the transfer of his
rights on it. Motivating his calculations is the expected use value of the value
object he receives in the exchange.


4   Open Issues
The extension of the value ascription ontology to also include exchange value
is straight forward. It hinges on exchange value being expressed in terms of
use value and elements of the REA business ontology. Nevertheless, there are a
number of open issues in the approach taken, including:
 – Are rights value objects in themselves? What is their ontological status?
 – What does it mean to use a commitment? In the ontology we say that a
   commitment is a value object and as such it can be given a use value. But
   how is it used? Is it to neutralize an obligation or is it to reserve another
   commitment or something else?


References
1. Andersson, B., Johannesson, P.: Ascribing value. In: Gordijn, J., Proper, E. (eds.)
   Proceedings of the 12th International Workshop on Value Modeling and Business
   Ontologies. pp. 28–36. CEUR (2018)
2. Geerts, G.L., McCarthy, W.E.: Policy-level specifications in REA enterprise infor-
   mation systems. Journal of Information Systems 20(2), 37–63 (2006)
3. Gordijn, J., Akkermans, J.M.: Value-based requirements engineering: exploring in-
   novative e-commerce ideas. Requirements Engineering 8(2), 114–134 (Jul 2003)
4. Guarino, N., Guizzardi, G.: Relationships and events: Towards a general theory of
   reification and truthmaking. In: AI*IA 2016 Advances in Artificial Intelligence. pp.
   237–249. Lecture Notes in Computer Science, Springer, Cham (Nov 2016)
5. Kenton, W.: Economic value. https://www.investopedia.com/terms/e/economic-
   value.asp (Dec 2018), accessed: 2019-1-17
6. Kenton, W.: Market value. https://www.investopedia.com/terms/m/marketvalue.asp
   (Dec 2018), accessed: 2019-1-17
7. Massin, O., Tieffenbach, E.: The metaphysics of economic exchanges. Journal of
   Social Ontology 3(2), 733 (Jan 2017)