=Paper=
{{Paper
|id=Vol-2495/paper14
|storemode=property
|title=Power Index-Based Semantics for Ranking Arguments in Abstract Argumentation Frameworks: an Overview
|pdfUrl=https://ceur-ws.org/Vol-2495/paper14.pdf
|volume=Vol-2495
|authors=Carlo Taticchi
|dblpUrl=https://dblp.org/rec/conf/aiia/Taticchi19
}}
==Power Index-Based Semantics for Ranking Arguments in Abstract Argumentation Frameworks: an Overview==
Power Index-Based Semantics for Ranking Arguments in Abstract Argumentation Frameworks: an Overview Carlo Taticchi1[0000−0003−1260−4672] Gran Sasso Science Institute, L’Aquila, Italy - carlo.taticchi@gssi.it Abstract. Ranking-based semantics for Abstract Argumentation Frame- works represent a well-established concept used for sorting arguments from the most to the least acceptable. This paper presents an overview of our ranking-based semantics that makes use of power indexes such as Shapley Value and Banzhaf Index. Such power index-based semantics is parametric to a chosen Dung semantics and inherits their properties. Keywords: Argumentation · Ranking Semantics · Cooperative Game Theory · Power Indexes 1 Introduction Argumentation Theory is a field of Artificial Intelligence that provides for- malisms for reasoning with conflicting information. Arguments from a knowl- edge base are modelled by Dung [11] as nodes in a directed graph, that we call Abstract Argumentation Framework (AF in short), where edges represent at- tacks. Many semantics have been defined in order to establish different kinds of acceptability (see [2] for a survey). All these semantics return two disjoint sets of arguments: “accepted” and “not accepted”. An additional level of acceptability is introduced in [9] with the reinstatement labelling, a semantics that marks as undecided the arguments that can be neither accepted nor rejected. Dividing the arguments into just three partitions could be not sufficient when dealing with very large AFs, so a different family of semantics has been defined for ob- taining a broader range of acceptability levels for the arguments. Each of the defined ranking-based semantics [1,3,6,10,13,16,17] focus on a different criterion for identifying the best arguments in an AF. In this paper, we give an overview of our work [4,5,6,7] towards the definition of a ranking-based semantics that relies on power indexes, like the Shapley Value and the Banzhaf index [14]. Our semantics is parametric to a chosen power index and allows for obtaining a ranking where the arguments are sorted according to their contribution to the acceptability of the other arguments in the various coalitions. To complete our study and support the research in this field, we also provide an online tool (ConArg1 ) capable of dealing with AFs and reasoning with our ranking-based semantics, besides classical ones. 1 ConArg Website: http://www.dmi.unipg.it/conarg/ Copyright c 2019 for this paper by its authors. Use permitted under Creative Commons License Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0). 114 C. Taticchi 2 Preliminaries on Argumentation and Power Indexes An Abstract Argumentation Framework [11] hA, Ri consists of a set of argu- ments A and the relations among them R ⊆ A × A. Such relations, which we call “attacks”, are interpreted as conflict conditions that allow for determining the arguments in A that are acceptable together (i.e., collectively). An argumenta- tion semantics is a criterion that establishes which are the acceptable arguments by considering the relations among them. The sets of accepted arguments with respect to a semantics are called extensions. Two leading characterisations can be found in the literature, namely extension-based [11] and labelling-based [9] semantics. While providing the same outcome in terms of accepted arguments, labelling-based semantics permits to differentiate between three levels of accept- ability. In detail, a labelling of an AF is a total function L : A → {in, out, undec}, with in(L) = {a ∈ A | L(a) = in}, out(L) = {a ∈ A | L(a) = out} and undec(L) = {a ∈ A | L(a) = undec}. L is a reinstatement labelling if and only if it satisfies the following conditions: – ∀a, b ∈ A, if a ∈ in(L) and (b, a) ∈ R then b ∈ out(L); – ∀a ∈ A, if a ∈ out(L) then ∃b ∈ A such that b ∈ in(L) and (b, a) ∈ R. A labelling-based semantics σ associates with an AF F = hA, Ri a subset of all the possible labellings for F, denoted as Lσ (F ). For instance, we say that a labelling L of F is admissible if and only if the attackers of each in argument are labelled out, and each out argument has at least one attacker that is in 2 . The accepted arguments of F , with respect to a certain semantics σ, are those labelled in by σ. We refer to sets of arguments that are labelled in, out or undec in at least one labelling of Lσ (F ) with in(Lσ ), out(Lσ ) and undec(Lσ ), respectively. In order to further discriminate among arguments, ranking-based seman- tics [8] can be used for sorting the arguments from the most to the least preferred. A ranking-based semantics associates with any F = hA, Ri a ranking