=Paper=
{{Paper
|id=Vol-2518/paper-FOUST1
|storemode=property
|title=No Chance for the Change Argument – A
Reply to Stout’s "The Category of
Occurrent Continuants"
|pdfUrl=https://ceur-ws.org/Vol-2518/paper-FOUST1.pdf
|volume=Vol-2518
|authors=Riccardo Baratella
|dblpUrl=https://dblp.org/rec/conf/jowo/Baratella19
}}
==No Chance for the Change Argument – A
Reply to Stout’s "The Category of
Occurrent Continuants"==
No Chance for the Change Argument – A Reply to Stout’s “The Category of Occurrent Continuants” Riccardo BARATELLA a,1 a University of Tübingen, Tübingen, Germany Abstract. Processes are occurrents that were, are, or will be happening. Moreover, either they endure (i.e., they continue) or they perdure. Stout [11] contends that they endure. His argument – the Change Argument, hereafter – is grounded in the claims that processes may change and that something may change if and only if it endures. I shall argue that the Change Argument does not succeed. In particular, I shall show that, if the Change Argument aims at being neutral between endurantism and perdurantism, then it is invalid. If, instead, his argument rejects the constraint of neutrality in favor of the assumption of endurance theory for processes, then it is valid, but circular. In either case, Stout’s Change Argument fails to establish that processes endure. Keywords. Processes, Change, Endurance Theory, Perdurance Theory. 1. Introduction In his “The Category of Occurrent Continuants”, Stout provides a metaphysical argument for the thesis that processes, that are a kind of occurrent, are continuants (i.e., that they endure) [11]. The argument is based on the claims that there are true sentences that describe changes in processes and that something may change if and only if it endures. In this paper, I argue that Stout’s argument (the Change Argument, hereafter) for the thesis that processes are continuants doesn’t succeed: if the argument aims at being neutral between endurantism and perdurantism, then it is not valid. If, on the other hand, this argument rejects neutrality and presupposes from the very beginning that processes endure, then it is valid, but circular. In either case, the Change Argument fails to establish that processes endure. This article is structured as follows. In Section 2, I provide some background. In Section 3, I present Stout’s Change Argument for the thesis that processes are continuants. In Section 4, I provide my argument to block the Change Argument. In 1 Riccardo Baratella, Department of Philosophy, University of Tübingen, Tübingen, Germany; E-mails: baratellariccardo@gmail.com; riccardo.baratella@philosophie.uni-tuebingen.de. Copyright © 2019 for this paper by its authors. Use permitted under Creative Commons License Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0). Section 5, I consider an objection to my reply and I show that it fails. In Section 6, I summarize the main conclusions of this paper.2 2. Background: Persistence and Change According to Stout, processes are things that are, were, or will be happening. Examples include my writing this article – something that is happening right now – or the concert that was happening yesterday. Processes are described or referred to in answering the progressive question: “What is (was, will be) happening?” The basic feature of expressions describing or referring to processes is the use of the progressive aspect. Stout contrasts processes with events. Events are things that happened or will happen. Examples include the explosion that will take place next year, and my winning the race that happened yesterday. Moreover, the basic feature of expressions describing or referring to events is the use of non-progressive aspect.3 Stout intends to show that the aforementioned linguistic distinction between expressions standing for events and those standing for processes corresponds to a substantive metaphysical distinction between events and processes themselves – a metaphysical distinction which is grounded in the different ways in which events and processes exist over time. Thus, according to Stout, there were two explosions yesterday: the one that was happening – a process – and the one that happened – an event. These explosions are different in that their ways of existing over time are different. Or this is what Stout aims to argue for through his Change Argument.4 As just mentioned, both events and processes exist over time – i.e., they persist. There are two main accounts of persistence. The first one is perdurance theory – the thesis that things of a certain kind perdure. Intuitively, something perdures if and only if it is extended in time and has different temporal part at different time – a different temporal part for each moment of time.5 The other account of persistence is endurance theory – the thesis that things of a certain kind endure. Intuitively, something endures if and only if it is ‘all’ there at each moment at which it exists. 6 Events, rather uncontroversially, perdure. However, Stout argues that, in this respect, processes differ from events: processes, he claims, endure. Stout provides the following characterization of the notions of being a perduring entity and being an enduring entity. According to Stout, perduring entities are things that primarily have their properties atemporally. Such a characterization can be explained via the perdurance analysis of sentences like “x has the property of sitting at t”. According to perdurance theory, the temporal qualification “at t” is part of the subject of the sentence, “x at t”, which denotes the t-temporal part of x. In turn, the predication of the 2 This article is a reply to the main metaphysical argument put forth in [11] for the thesis that processes endure. I shall examine neither other independent, linguistic motivations for the same thesis discussed in [11, p. 56], nor other arguments for this thesis discussed in other works (e.g. [2] and [10]). 3 [9] argues that this way of articulating the distinction between events and processes cannot be really defended. Indeed, she takes to be a metaphysical-com-semantical rule that if an event e has happened by t, and e was not instantaneous, then e must have been happening at some time prior t. If one accepts such a rule, then Stout’s characterization implies that every non-instantaneous event is also a process. But, then, the metaphysical distinction between events and processes seems undermined. 4 In addition to Stouts, many other philosophers argue for a metaphysical distinction between events and processes. See, for instance, [2], [9] and references therein. 5 [3], [4], and [7] argue that objects perdure. 6 [1] and [6] argue that objects endure. property sitting has no temporal connotation at all: the property is atemporally exemplified by the temporal part x-at-t. 7 This means that the exemplification of the property sitting by the t-temporal part of x is not relativized to times: the exemplification involves only that temporal part and the property of sitting. According to perdurance theory (and this is the meaning of Stout’s characterization of perduring entities as things that primarily have their properties atemporally), the atemporal exemplification is basic and temporal predications, such as “sitting at t”, are analyzed in terms of it. As a result, a sentence like “x has property P at time t” is true if and only if x has atemporally a t- temporal part that has atemporally the property P. By contrast, enduring entities are things that primarily have their properties at times. Let me clarify such a characterization by considering “x has the property of sitting at t”. Within endurance theory, the subject of the sentence is simply “x”, which denotes a ‘three-dimensional’ entity x. The temporal qualification belongs to the predicate which results in “having the property of sitting at t”. Such a predicate must, now, be analyzed. According to Stout (and this is the meaning of his characterization of enduring entities as things that primarily have their properties at times), such a predicate must be analyzed via a notion of exemplification which is fundamentally temporal. 8 In particular, he adopts the Tensing the Copula strategy, according to which the temporal qualification modifies the relation of exemplification (while keeping the subject not tensed). As a result, the previous sentence is analyzed as “x has-at-t the property of sitting”.9 In general, a sentence containing a temporal predication like “x has property P at time t” is true if and only if x has-at-t the property P. Crucially, Stout assumes that objects endure and that they can change over time (p. 44) – where the notion of change Stout adopts is characterized as follows: (Change) Something changes if and only if this thing has a property at one time and at a later time the very same thing does not have that very property. Stout notes that, from (Change), it follows that changeable properties are those properties that a thing can only have at a time and not atemporally. So, with (Change) in place, perduring entities cannot change. Indeed, consider an event such as Prior’s life. This event has atemporally different temporal parts with incompatible properties. Now, since Prior’s life and its temporal parts have their properties and enter in their relations atemporally, they cannot fail to do so. Hence, Prior’s life and its temporal parts cannot satisfy (Change). Given that, it is possible to derive the following conclusion: (The Change Constraint) Something endures if and only if it may change over time. 3. The Change Argument Stout argues that processes persist by enduring rather than by perduring – i.e., that they primarily have their properties at a time rather than timelessly. The argument he provides 7 For the notion of atemporal exemplification see [8, p. 122], [3, pp. 13-14], [7, p. 56), and [11, pp. 46-47]. 8 Endurance theory rejects the notion atemporal exemplification as incomplete or unintelligible. Indeed, suppose that x is both sitting today and not-sitting tomorrow. Suppose also that x endures. If we adopted the notion of atemporal exemplification, we would get that x is both sitting and not-sitting. Contradiction. 9 [5] argues against the tensing the copula analysis. Let us concede that it is a workable position. aims at establishing that processes endure – and, so, his argument aims at being neutral between endurantism and perdurantism. Now, Stout asks to consider a fight that went on outside his house between 11.55 p.m. and 12.05 a.m. last night. That fight was happening at midnight. Hence, it is a process. Stout’s argument – call it “the Change Argument” – is the following [11, p. 50]: At first it was quite brutal, but after a few minutes it became less ferocious, though as if to make up for this, it got gradually more noisy until the police arrived and stopped it. On the face of it it is a thing that continues through time and has different properties at different times. Given Stout’s framework, the Change Argument can be reconstructed as follows: (1) At first, the fight was quite brutal, but after a few minutes it become gradually less ferocious; meanwhile, it got gradually more noisy until it stopped. According to Stout, on the face of it, from (1) it follows: (2) The fight is a thing that continues through time and it has different properties at different times.10 By (Change) and (2), it follows: (3) The fight changes. By (3) and (The Change Constraint), we get: (4) The fight endures – i.e., the fight primarily has its properties at a time rather than timelessly. 4. No Chance for the Change Argument My reply to Stout’s Change Argument is structured along three steps: (P1), (P2), and (P3). (P1) In order to understand an argument, we need to be able to interpret its sentences, i.e. to give their truth-conditions. Moreover, it is plausible to assume that the truth- conditions of sentences involving notions such as continuity over time or persistence require, implicitly or explicitly, the assumption of a theory of persistence. (P2) Consider premise (1). By (P1), its truth-conditions require the assumption of a specific theory of persistence for processes. Since processes either endure or perdure, and since the Change Argument aims at being neutral between an endurantist and a perdurantist reading of (1), we can adopt perdurance theory and provide the truth- conditions of (1) within such a theory. As a result, there is a perdurance model M that accounts for the supposed truth of (1). (P3) Since (1) is true in M, the other claims in the Change Argument (i.e. claims (2)- (4)) must be true in M for the Change Argument to be valid. However, (3) cannot be true in such a model. Stout, then, faces a dilemma: if he keeps fix the neutrality of his argument, this argument is invalid. If, on the other hand, he rejects neutrality in favor of the assumption of endurance theory for processes, his argument is valid, but circular. In either case, the Change Argument fails to establish that processes endure. 10 By saying that the fight continues through time, Stout cannot mean that it endures. If he meant it just on the basis of (1), he would simply state his intuitions. But, whether or not the fight continues by enduring – instead of by perduring – has to be established by some argument. Hence, I will take such an expression to mean that the fight persists through time. (P1) In order to understand an argument, we need to be able to interpret its sentences, i.e. to give their truth-conditions. Moreover, it is plausible to assume that the truth- conditions of sentences involving notions such as continuity over time or persistence require, implicitly or explicitly, the assumption of a theory of persistence. The meaning of assumption (P1) can be clarified by an example. We cannot read off directly from the surface of an ordinary sentence whether the entities it is about persist by enduring or by perduring. In fact, suppose not to have settled whether objects endure or perdure. Then, simply from the sentence “John swims at t” we cannot establish whether John endures rather than he perdures. If John perdures, then the previous sentence means that he is extended in time and he has a t-temporal part that swims. But, if John endures, it means that numerically the same entity is ‘wholly’ present at more than one time, and that at one of these times, t, he swims. The sentence by itself does not impose one account of persistence. Instead, in providing the truth-conditions of a sentence, such a sentence must be interpreted within a specific theory of persistence that applies to the entities it is about. This is not to say that we cannot offer considerations in favor of a particular theory of persistence on the basis of natural language.11 For instance, the intuitive truth-value or the intended meaning of certain ordinary talks may be explicable only within a particular theory of persistence. But, these kinds of arguments compare the truth- conditions offered by different theories of persistence, and then they show that one account fares better than the others. In any case, they do adopt one particular theory of persistence in providing the truth-conditions for ordinary talks. Ordinary talks alone cannot do much. (P2) Consider premise (1). By (P1), its truth-conditions require the assumption of a specific theory of persistence for processes. Since processes either endure or perdure, and since the Change Argument aims at being neutral between an endurantist and a perdurantist reading of (1), we can adopt perdurance theory and provide the truth- conditions of (1) within such a theory. As a result, there is a perdurance model M that accounts for the supposed truth of (1). The Change Argument aims at establishing that processes endure – and, so, it aims at being neutral between endurantism and perdurantism. Thus, it does not restrict the admissible interpretations of (1) to those formulated within a specific theory of persistence. This means that we can interpret (1) within any theory of persistence we like. So, let us adopt perdurance theory for processes and provide the truth-conditions for (1) within such a theory. Perdurance theory provides the following account for both our ordinary talks about how a thing is like at a moment of time, and our ordinary talks about how a thing is like at different moments of time. A sentence like “x is P at t” is true if and only if x has (atemporally) a t-temporal part that has (atemporally) the property of being P. Whereas, a sentence like “a persisting x is P now, and not-P yesterday” is true if and only if x has (atemporally) a now-temporal part that has (atemporally) the property of being P, and x has (atemporally) a yesterday-temporal part that has (atemporally) the property of being not-P. Hence, the truth-conditions for (1) within the perdurance theory are as follows: (1) At first, the fight was quite brutal, but after a few minutes it become gradually less ferocious; meanwhile, it got gradually more noisy until it stopped 11 See, for instance, [1], [3, pp.12-13, 37-38], and [12]. is true if and only if the fight has (atemporally) a t1-temporal part that has (atemporally) the properties of being brutal with grade n and being noisy with grade p and has (atemporally) a successive t2-temporal part that has (atemporally) the properties of being brutal with grade m (with m