=Paper=
{{Paper
|id=Vol-3002/paper11
|storemode=property
|title=Timed Concurrent Language for Argumentation
|pdfUrl=https://ceur-ws.org/Vol-3002/paper11.pdf
|volume=Vol-3002
|authors=Stefano Bistarelli,Maria Chiara Meo,Carlo Taticchi
|dblpUrl=https://dblp.org/rec/conf/cilc/BistarelliMT21
}}
==Timed Concurrent Language for Argumentation==
Timed Concurrent Language for Argumentation? Stefano Bistarelli1 , Maria Chiara Meo2 , and Carlo Taticchi1 1 Università degli Studi di Perugia, Italy [stefano.bistarelli,carlo.taticchi]@unipg.it 2 Università degli Studi G. d’Annunzio di Chieti-Pescara, Italy mariachiara.meo@unich.it Abstract. Argumentation Theory offers formalisms for the study of rea- soning processes taking place between intelligent entities. In this context, time is a crucial factor: in a real-world environment, activities have a de- termined temporal duration and the behaviour of agents is influenced by the actions previously taken. While agent-based modelling languages naturally implement concurrency and time constraints, the currently available languages for argumentation do not allow to explicitly model this type of behaviours. In this paper, we propose a language for mod- elling concurrent interaction between agents that also allows the speci- fication of temporal intervals in which particular actions occur. Such a language, that we call Timed Concurrent Language for Argumentation, allows agents to communicate with each other and to reason on the ac- ceptability of their beliefs with respect to a given time interval. We also show how Timed Abstract Argumentation Frameworks can be modelled by combining time and concurrency. Keywords: Argumentation Theory · Timed concurrent language · Se- mantics. 1 Introduction Argumentation Theory pursues the objective of studying how conclusions can be reached, starting from a set of assumptions, through a process of logical rea- soning. This process is very similar to the human way of thinking and involves features which can be traced to a form of dialogue between two (or more) peo- ple. Abstract Argumentation Frameworks [16], AFs in short, are used to study the acceptability of arguments according to given selection criteria. Formalisms like Timed Abstract Argumentation Frameworks (TAFs) [10,14,15] have been proposed to meet the need for including the notion of time into argumentation processes. Time is a particularly important aspect of cooperative environments: in many “real-life” applications, the activities have a temporal duration (that can be even interrupted) and the coordination of such activities has to take into consideration this timeliness property. The interacting actors are mutually ? Copyright c 2021 for this paper by its authors. Use permitted under Creative Com- mons License Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0). influenced by their actions, meaning that agent A reacts accordingly to the tim- ing and quantitative aspects related to the behaviour of agent B, and vice versa. Moreover, the information brought forward by debating agents that interact in a dynamic environment can be affected by time constraints, limiting, for instance, the influence of some arguments in the system to a certain time lapse. A mech- anism for handling time is therefore required to better model the behaviour of intelligent agents involved in argumentation processes. With this paper, we introduce the Timed Concurrent language for Argumen- tation (tcla), a timed extension of cla [5,6], which models dynamic interactions between agents and uses notions from Argumentation Theory to reason about shared knowledge. We provide both the syntax and the operational semantics. Coordinating agents that need to take decisions both on arguments and attacks and time events may benefit from this language. Such agents can be used, for in- stance, to implement TAFs, namely extended AFs in which arguments are only available for a given temporal interval. The language we present is well suited for this kind of tasks, as Section 4 shows with examples. More complex dynamics could also be considered: for example, an argument could be made available only if specific conditions are met, and agents could be given priorities in introducing arguments for certain time intervals. tcla is based on the hypothesis of bounded asynchrony [25]: any computa- tion takes a bounded period of time rather than being instantaneous as in the concurrent synchronous languages esterel [3], lustre [17], signal [20] and Statecharts [18]. Time itself is measured by a discrete global clock, i.e., the internal clock of the tcla process. In tcla, we directly introduce a timed interpre- tation of the programming constructs by identifying a time-unit with the time needed for the execution of a basic action (that can be an addition, a removal or a check of arguments/attacks, or a semantical test of arguments), and by interpreting action prefixing (→) as the next-time operator. An explicit timing primitive is also introduced in order to allow for the specification of timeouts. Note that we consider a paradigm where parallel operations are expressed in term of maximal parallelism. According to the maximal parallelism policy, at each moment, every enabled agent of the system is activated, while in the inter- leaving paradigm only one of the enabled agents is executed instead. By using maximal parallelism, time passes for all the parallel processes involved in a com- putation. This approach, analogous to the one adopted in [8,4,25], is different from the one of [9], where time elapsing is interpreted in terms of interleaving, although assuming maximal parallelism for actions depending on time. Our pro- posal is also different from the one in [11], where time does not elapse for timeout constructs. The rest of the paper is organised as follows: in Section 2 we summarise the most important background notions and frameworks from which tcla derives. In Section 3 we present tcla and the operational semantics of its agents. Section 4 exemplifies the use of timed paradigms in tcla and shows an application example of how a TAF can be dynamically instantiated, highlighting the relation between tcla and TAFs. Section 5 describes some related work, and Section 6 concludes the paper by also indicating future research lines. 2 Background Argumentation Theory aims to understand and model the human natural fashion of reasoning, allowing one to deal with uncertainty in non-monotonic (defeasible) reasoning. In his seminal paper [16], Dung defines the building blocks of abstract argumentation. Definition 1 (AFs). Let U be the set of all available arguments3 , which we refer to as the “universe”. An Abstract Argumentation Framework is a pair hArg, Ri where Arg ⊆ U is a set of adopted arguments and R is a binary relation on Arg. For two arguments a, b ∈ Arg, the notation (a, b) ∈ R represents an attack directed from a against b. We define the sets of arguments that attack (and that are attacked by) another argument as follows. Definition 2 (Attacks). Let F = hArg, Ri be an AF, a ∈ Arg and S ⊆ Arg. We define + S the+ sets aF− = {b S ∈ Arg | (a, b) ∈ R}, a− F = {b ∈ Arg | (b, a) ∈ R}, + − SF = a∈S aF and SF = a∈S aF (we will omit the subscript F when it is clear from the context). Definition 3 (Acceptable Argument). Given an AF F = hArg, Ri, an ar- gument a ∈ Arg is acceptable with respect to D ⊆ Arg if and only if ∀b ∈ Arg such that (b, a) ∈ R, ∃c ∈ D such that (c, b) ∈ R, and we say that a is defended from D. By using the notion of defence as a criterion for distinguishing acceptable sets of arguments (extensions) in the framework, one can further refine the set of selected “good” arguments. The goal is to establish which are the accept- able arguments according to a certain semantics, namely a selection criterion. Non-accepted arguments are rejected. Different kinds of semantics have been introduced [16,1] that reflect qualities which are likely to be desirable. We first recall definitions for the extension-based semantics [16], namely admissible, com- plete, stable, semi-stable, preferred, and grounded semantics (denoted with adm, com, stb, sst, prf and gde, respectively, and generically with σ). Definition 4 (Extension-based semantics). Let F = hArg, Ri be an AF. A set E ⊆ Arg is conflict-free in F , denoted E ∈ Scf (F ), when there are no a, b ∈ E such that (a, b) ∈ R. For E ∈ Scf (F ) we have that: – E ∈ Sadm (F ) when each a ∈ E is defended by E 4 ; 3 The set U is not present in the original definition by Dung and we introduce it for our convenience. 4 If E ∈ Sadm (F ) we say that E is an admissible extension of F . Analogously for the other semantics. – E ∈ Scom (F ) when E ∈ Sadm (F ) and ∀a ∈ Arg defended by E, a ∈ E; – E ∈ Sstb (F ) when ∀a ∈ Arg \ E, ∃b ∈ E such that (b, a) ∈ R; – E ∈ Ssst (F ) when E ∈ Scom (F ) and E ∪ E + is maximal; – E ∈ Sprf (F ) when E ∈ Sadm (F ) and E is maximal; – E ∈ Sgde (F ) when E ∈ Scom (F ) and E is minimal. Besides enumerating the extensions for a certain semantics σ, one of the most common tasks performed on AFs is to decide whether an argument a is accepted in some extension of Sσ (F ) or in all extensions of Sσ (F ). In the former case, we say that a is credulously accepted with respect to σ; in the latter, a is instead sceptically accepted with respect to σ. Example 1. In Figure 1 we provide an example of AF where sets of extensions are given for all the mentioned semantics: Scf (F ) = {{}, {a}, {b}, {c}, {d}, {a, c}, {a, d}, {b, d}}, Sadm (F ) = {{}, {a}, {c}, {d}, {a, c}, {a, d}}, Scom (F ) = {{a}, {a, c}, {a, d}}, Sprf (F ) = {{a, c}, {a, d}}, Sstb (F ) = Ssst (F ) = {{a, d}}, and Sgde (F ) = {{a}}. To conclude the example, we want to point out that argument a is sceptically accepted with respect to the complete semantics, since it appears in all three subsets of Scom (F ). On the other hand, arguments c, that is in just one complete extension, is credulously accepted with respect to the complete semantics. Fig. 1. Example of abstract argumentation framework. Many of the above-mentioned semantics (such as the admissible and the com- plete ones) exploit the notion of defence in order to decide whether an argument is part of an extension or not. The phenomenon for which an argument is ac- cepted in some extension because it is defended by another argument belonging to that extension is known as reinstatement [12]. In the same paper, Caminada also gives a definition for a reinstatement labelling. Definition 5 (Reinstatement labelling). Let F = hArg, Ri be an AF and L = {in, out, undec}. A labelling of F is a total function L : Arg → L. We define in(L) = {a ∈ Arg | L(a) = in}, out(L) = {a ∈ Arg | L(a) = out} and undec(L) = {a ∈ Arg | L(a) = undec}. We say that L is a reinstatement labelling if and only if it satisfies the following: – ∀a ∈ Arg : a ∈ in(L) ⇐⇒ ∀b ∈ Arg | (b, a) ∈ R : b ∈ out(L) – ∀a ∈ Arg : a ∈ out(L) ⇐⇒ ∃b ∈ Arg | (b, a) ∈ R ∧ b ∈ in(L) Fig. 2. Example of reinstatement labelling. In other words, an argument is labelled in if all its attackers are labelled out, and it is labelled out if at least an in node attacks it. In all other cases, the argument is labelled undec. A labelling-based semantics [1] associates with an AF a subset of all the possible labellings. In Figure 2 we show an example of reinstatement labelling on an AF in which arguments a and c highlighted in green are in, red ones (b and d) are out, and the the yellow argument e (that attacks itself) is undec. Table 1. Reinstatement labelling vs semantics. Labelling restrictions Semantics no restrictions complete empty undec stable minimal undec semi-stable maximal in preferred maximal out preferred maximal undec grounded minimal in grounded minimal out grounded Given a labelling L, it is possible to identify a correspondence with the extension-based semantics [1]. In particular, the set of in arguments coincides with a complete extension, while other semantics can be obtained through re- strictions on the labelling as shown in Table 1. The notion of time can be included into the reasoning model of AFs by considering temporal intervals [15] defined as follows. Definition 6 (Temporal Interval). A temporal interval is a pair built from t1 , t2 ∈ Z in one of the following ways: – [t1 , t1 ], denoting the moment t1 ; – [t1 , ∞), a set of moments formed by all the numbers in Z greater than or equal to t1 ; – (−∞, t2 ], a set of moments formed by all the numbers in Z smaller than or equal to t2 ; – [t1 , t2 ], a set of moments formed by all the numbers in Z from t1 to t2 (both included); – (−∞, ∞), denoting a set of moments formed by all the numbers in Z. The set of all the intervals defined over Z ∪ {−∞, ∞} is denoted Υ . In Timed Argumentation Frameworks [14,15], each argument is associated with temporal intervals that express the period of time in which the argument is available. Definition 7 (TAFs). A timed abstract argumentation framework is a tuple hArg, R, Avi where Arg ⊆ U is a set of adopted arguments belonging to the uni- verse U , R5 is a binary relation on Arg, and Av : Arg → ℘(Υ ) is the availability function for timed arguments. We illustrate in Figure 3 an example of the behaviour of timed arguments taken from [15], with availability function defined as Av(a) = {[10, 40], [60, 75]}, Av(b) = {[30, 50]}, Av(c) = {[20, 40], [45, 55], [60, 70]}, Av(d) = {[47, 65]} and Av(e) = {(−∞, 44]}. Note that attack relations in a TAF never change, but are only considered when availability of both the attacker and the attacked arguments overlaps (alternatively, we can consider attacks to blink together with the arguments they connect). We can imagine the modifications at a given instant t taking place simultaneously, as if every argument of the TAF was handled (made available/not available) by a different agent. 10 40 60 75 a 30 50 b 20 40 45 55 60 70 c 47 65 d 44 e time Fig. 3. Example of timed abstract argumentation framework. Given a semantics σ, the set of acceptable arguments in a TAF can be com- puted with respect to a certain moment t by only considering arguments (and attacks) available at t. For example, in the TAF of Figure 3, the singleton {b} is an admissible extension for t ∈ (41, 44), that is when b itself is available and its attacker c is not. 5 Note that in certain time intervals, attacks could be defined between arguments not currently available in the TAF. 3 tcla Syntax and Semantics The syntax of our Timed Concurrent Language for Argumentation, tcla, is pre- sented in Table 2, where, as usual, P , C, A and E denote a generic process, a sequence of procedure declarations (or clauses), a generic agent and a generic guarded agent, respectively. Moreover t ∈ N ∪ {+∞}. In Tables 3 and 4, then, we give the definitions for the transition rules. P ::= C.A C ::= p(a, l, σ, i) :: A | C.C A ::= success | f ailure | add(Arg, R) → A | rmv(Arg, R) → A | E | AkA | ∃x A | p(a, l, σ, i) E ::= testc,t (a, l, σ) → A | tests,t (a, l, σ) → A | checkt (Arg, R) → A | E + E | E +P E | EkG E Table 2. tcla syntax. Communication between tcla agents is implemented via shared memory, sim- ilarly to cla [5] and CC [26], and opposed to other languages (e.g., CSP [19] and CCS [23]) based on message passing. In the following, we denote by E the class of guarded agents and by E0 the class of guarded agents such that all outermost guards have t = 0 (note that a Boolean syntactic category could be introduced in replacement of E0 to better handle guards and allow for finer distinctions). In a tcla process P = C.A, A is the initial agent, to be executed in the context of the set of declarations C. The operational model of tcla processes can be formally described by a transi- tion system T = (Conf , −→), where we assume that each transition step exactly takes one time-unit. Configurations (in) Conf are pairs consisting of a process and an AF F = hArg, Ri representing the common knowledge base. The tran- sition relation −→⊆ Conf × Conf is the least relation satisfying the rules in Tables 3 and 4, and it characterises the (temporal) evolution of the system. So, hA, F i −→ hA0 , F 0 i means that, if at time t we have the process A and the framework F , then at time t + 1 we have the process A0 and the framework F 0 . In Tables 3 and 4 we have omitted the symmetric rules for the choice oper- ator + and for the two parallel composition operators k and kG . Indeed, + is commutative, so E1 + E2 produces the same result as (that is, is congruent to) E2 + E1 . The same is also true for k and kG . Note that +, k and kG are also associative. Moreover success and f ailure are the identity and the absorbing elements under the parallel composition k, respectively (namely for each agent A, we have that Aksuccess and Akf ailure are the agents A and f ailure, re- spectively). In the following, we will usually write a tcla process P = C.A as the corresponding agent A, omitting C when not required by the context. hadd(Arg 0 , R0 ) → A, hArg, Rii −→ hA, hArg ∪ Arg 0 , R ∪ R00 ii Ad where R00 = {(a, b) ∈ R0 | a, b ∈ Arg ∪ Arg 0 } hrmv(Arg 0 , R0 ) → A, hArg, Rii −→ hA, hArg \ Arg 0 , R \ {R0 ∪ R00 }ii Re where R00 = {(a, b) ∈ R | a ∈ Arg 0 ∨ b ∈ Arg 0 } Arg 0 ⊆ Arg ∧ R0 ⊆ R t > 0 Ch (1) hcheckt (Arg 0 , R0 ) → A, hArg, Rii −→ hA, hArg, Rii Arg 0 6⊆ Arg ∨ R0 6⊆ R t > 0 Ch (2) hcheckt (Arg 0 , R0 ) → A, hArg, Rii −→ hcheckt−1 (Arg 0 , R0 ) → A, hArg, Rii hcheck0 (Arg 0 , R0 ) → A, F i −→ hf ailure, F i Ch (3) ∃L ∈ Sσ (F ) | l ∈ L(a) t > 0 CT (1) htestc,t (a, l, σ) → A, F i −→ hA, F i ∀L ∈ Sσ (F ).l 6∈ L(a) t > 0 CT (2) htestc,t (a, l, σ) → A, F i −→ htestc,t−1 (a, l, σ) → A, F i htestc,0 (a, l, σ) → A, F i −→ hf ailure, F i CT (3) ∀L ∈ Sσ (F ).l ∈ L(a) t > 0 ST (1) htests,t (a, l, σ) → A, F i −→ hA, F i ∃L ∈ Sσ (F ) | l 6∈ L(a) t > 0 ST (2) htests,t (a, l, σ) → A, F i −→ htests,t−1 (a, l, σ) → A, F i htests,0 (a, l, σ) −→ A, F i −→ hf ailure, F i ST (3) hE1 , F i −→ hA1 , F i, E1 6∈ E0 , A1 6∈ E If (1) hE1 +P E2 , F i −→ hA1 , F i hE1 , F i −→ hE10 , F i, E1 6∈ E0 , E10 ∈ E E1 ∈ E0 , hE2 , F i −→ hA2 , F i If (2) hE1 +P E2 , F i −→ hE10 +P E2 , F i hE1 +P E2 , F i −→ hA2 , F i Table 3. tcla operational semantics (part 1/2). hE1 , F i −→ hA1 , F i, hE2 , F i −→ hA2 , F i, E1 , E2 6∈ E0 , A1 6∈ E GP (1) hE1 kG E2 , F i −→ hA1 kA2 , F i hE1 , F i −→ hE10 , F i, hE2 , F i −→ hE20 , F i, E1 , E2 6∈ E0 , E10 , E20 ∈ E GP (2) hE1 kG E2 , F i −→ hE10 kG E20 , F i E1 ∈ E0 , hE2 , F i −→ hA2 , F i GP (3) hE1 kG E2 , F i −→ hA2 , F i hA1 , F i −→ hA01 , F 0 i, hA2 , F i −→ hA02 , F 00 i Pa hA1 kA2 , F i −→ hA01 kA02 , ∗(F, F 0 , F 00 )i hE1 , F i −→ hA1 , F i, E1 6∈ E0 , A1 6∈ E E1 ∈ E0 , hE2 , F i −→ hA2 , F i ND (1) hE1 + E2 , F i −→ hA1 , F i hE1 + E2 , F i −→ hA2 , F i hE1 , F i −→ hE10 , F i, hE2 , F i −→ hE20 , F i, E1 , E2 6∈ E0 , E10 , E20 ∈ E ND (2) hE1 + E2 , F i −→ hE10 + E20 , F i hA[y/x], F i −→ hA0 , F 0 i with y ∈ U \ Arg HA h∃x A, F i −→ hA0 , F 0 i hp(b, m, γ, j), F i −→ hA[b/a, m/l, γ/σ, j/i], F i when p(a, l, σ, i) :: A PC Table 4. tcla operational semantics (part 2/2). Suppose we have an agent A whose knowledge base is represented by a frame- work F = hArg, Ri. An add(Arg 0 , R0 ) action performed by the agent results in the addition of a set of arguments Arg 0 ⊆ U (where U is the universe) and a set of relations R0 to the AF F . When performing an addition, (possibly) new arguments are taken from U \ Arg. We want to make clear that the tuple (Arg 0 , R0 ) is not an AF, indeed it is possible to have Arg 0 = ∅ and R0 6= ∅. However, the structure of the shared store after an add operation is guaranteed to be an AF compliant with Definition 1, since only attacks between arguments in Arg ∪ Args0 are added to R. Intuitively, rmv(Arg, R) allows to specify arguments and/or attacks to be removed from the knowledge base. The removal of an argument from an AF also involves removing all attack relations outgoing from and incoming to that argument, thus making F preserve the structure of an AF. Trying to remove an argument (or an attack) which does not exist in F will have no consequences. The testc,t (a, l, σ) → A, tests,t (a, l, σ) → A and checkt (Arg, R) → A con- structs are explicit timing primitives that allow for the specification of timeouts. In fact, in timed applications often one cannot wait indefinitely for an event. Thus, a timed language should allow us to specify that, in case a given time bound is exceeded (i.e. a timeout occurs), the wait is interrupted and an alter- native action is taken. The operator checkt (Arg 0 , R0 ) (rules Ch (1)-(3) in Table 3) realises a timed construct and is used to verify whether, in a given time interval, the specified arguments and attack relations are contained in the set of arguments and attacks of the knowledge base, without introducing any further change. If t > 0 and the check is positive, the operation succeeds and the agent checkt (Arg 0 , R0 ) → A can perform an action in the agent A (rule Ch (1)). If t > 0 but the check is not satisfied, then the control is repeated at the next time instant and the value of the counter t is decreased (rule Ch (2)). Axiom Ch (3) shows that, if the timeout is exceeded, i.e., the counter t has reached the value of 0, then the process checkt (Arg 0 , R0 ) → A fails. The rules for credulous tests CT (1)-(3) and sceptical tests SC (1)-(3) in Table 3 are similar to rules Ch (1)-(3) described before. Observe that we have two distinct test operations, both requiring the specification of an argument a ∈ Arg, a label l ∈ {in, out, undec}6 and a semantics σ ∈ {adm, com, stb, sst, prf, gde}. The credulous testc (a, l, σ) succeeds if there exists at least one extension of Sσ (F ) whose corresponding labelling L is such that L(a) = l. Similarly, the sceptical tests (a, l, σ) succeeds if a is labelled l in all possible labellings L ∈ Sσ (F ). The operator +P (If (1)-(2) in Table 3) is left-associative and realises an if-then-else construct: if we have E1 +P E2 (with E1 , E2 ∈ E) and the guards of E1 succeed, than E1 will be always chosen over E2 , even if also the guards of E2 succeed. So, in order for E2 to be selected, it has to be the only one such that its guards succeed and will be selected only after E1 fails. If the guards of E1 do not fail, the execution can either move to any consequent agent A1 which does not belong to E, or proceed with E10 +P E2 ∈ E. The guarded parallelism GP (1)-(3) in Table 4 is designed to allow all the operations for which the guards in the inner expression are satisfied. In more detail, the guards of E1 kG E2 succeed when either the guards of E1 , E2 or both succeed and all the operations that can be executed are executed. This behaviour is different both from classical parallelism (for which all the agents have to succeed in order for the parallel agent to succeed) and from nondeterminism (that only selects one branch). The remaining operators are classical concurrency compositions: the rule parallelism Pa in Table 4 models the parallel composition operator in terms of maximal parallelism. By transition rules, an agent in a parallel composition obtained through k succeeds only if all the agents succeed. In our implementation of rule Pa, we use ∗(F, F 0 , F 00 ) := (F 0 ∩ F 00 ) ∪ ((F 0 ∪ F 00 ) \ F ) to handle parallel additions and removals of arguments7 . In particular, if an argument a is added and removed at the same moment (e.g., trough the program add({a}, {}) → success k rmv({a}, {}) → success), we have two possible outcomes: if a was not 6 Other labelling semantics could be considered where undec arguments are further divided into “don’t know” and “don’t care” [7]. 7 Union, intersection and difference between AFs are intended as the union, intersec- tion and difference of their sets of arguments and attacks, respectively. present in the knowledge base, then the add operation gains priority over the rmv one, since a ∈ ((F 0 ∪ F 00 ) \ F ); on the other hand, when a was already in the shared memory, we have that a 6∈ ((F 0 ∪ F 00 ) \ F ), and a is removed. Any agent composed through + (rules ND (1)-(2)) is chosen if its guards succeed; the existential quantifier ∃x A of rule HA behaves like agent A where variables (arguments) in x are local to A. The procedure call (rule PC) has four parameters that allow the implementation of operators which takes into account an argument, a semantic label (in/out/undec), a semantics σ and a time interval i, respectively. In the following we provide the definition for the observables of the language, which considers the traces of successful or failed terminating computations that the agent A can perform for each tcla process P = C.A. Given a transition relation −→, we denote by −→∗ its reflexive and transitive closure. Definition 8 (Observables for tcla). Let P = C.A be a tcla process. We define Oio (P ) = {F1 · · · Fn · ss | hA, F1 i−→∗ hsuccess, Fn i} ∪ {F1 · · · Fn · ff | hA, F1 i−→∗ hf ailure, Fn i}. 4 Modelling TAFs In the context of argumentation, the possibility to include time in the reason- ing processes conducted by intelligent agents allows for modelling dynamic be- haviours, such as, for instance, the addition and the removal of information at precise moments from a knowledge base. Agents using tcla constructs and availability functions in TAFs regulate the existence of arguments in a similar way; in particular, we can imagine each agent having control over an argument of the TAF. This result is showed by providing explicitly a translation from a TAF into a tcla process. In the following, given I ⊆ Υ , I is ordered if there is no [t1 , t2 ] ∈ I such that t2 < t1 and for each i1 , i2 ∈ I, we have that i1 and i2 are disjoint and non-consecutive. Without loss of generality, we consider only ordered sets of intervals. Moreover, given I 6= ∅ we denote by (−∞, +∞) if (−∞, +∞) ∈ I (−∞, t] if (−∞, t] ∈ I f irst(I) = [t, +∞) if {[t, +∞)} = I [t1 , t2 ] otherwise where [t1 , t2 ] ∈ I is such that for each T 0 ∈ I, where T 0 = [t01 , t02 ] or T 0 = [t01 +∞), t1 < t01 . Moreover, we denote by continue(I) = I \ f irst(I). Finally, given a ∈ Arg and a binary relation R defined over Arg, we denote by R|a = {(a, b) | (a, b) ∈ R} ∪ {(b, a) | (b, a) ∈ R}. To ease the translation, we use sleep(t) → A, with t ≥ 0, as a shortcut for ( A if t ≤ 0 check1 ({}, {}) → (sleep(t − 1) → A) otherwise The agent sleep(t) → A, with t ≥ 0, executes the check operation for exactly t times and then the agent A is executed. Practically, sleep(t) lets the agent A wait for t instants of time. In the following we assume that for each [t1 , t2 ] ∈ S, t1 > 0. Definition 9 (Translation). The translation of a TAF h{a1 , . . . , an }, R, Avi is T (h{a1 , . . . , an }, R, Avi) = Tadd (0, a1 , R|a1 , Av(a1 ))k · · · kTadd (0, an , R|an , Av(an )) where success if S = ∅ add({a}, R) → success if S = {(−∞, +∞)} Tadd (t, a, R, S) = sleep(tin − t − 1) → (add({a}, R) → Trmv (t, a, R, S)) otherwise and success if S = {[t1 , +∞)} f in − tin ) → sleep(t Trmv (t, a, R, S) = (rmv({a}, {}) → Tadd (tf in + 1, a, R, continue(S))) otherwise where ( 1 if f irst(S) = (−∞, t2 ] tin = t1 if f irst(S) = [t1 , t2 ] or f irst(S) = [t1 , +∞) and tf in = t2 if f irst(S) = (−∞, t2 ] or f irst(S) = [t1 , t2 ]. Theorem 1. The translation T of a TAF produces a tcla program such that, at any instant of time t > 0, the arguments in the store are all and only the arguments available at t in the original TAF. Corollary 1. Given a tcla program produced by a translation T of a TAF, the set of arguments in the store accepted with respect to a semantics σ at a given instant of time t > 0 coincides with the set of extensions identified by σ at moment t on the original TAF . Example 2. Consider the TAF of Figure 3. By following previous translation T 0 , the availability of its timed arguments for each time instant t > 0 can be simulated by a tcla process that modifies the store by adding and removing part of the underlying framework. We use five agents in parallel (see Table 5), each of which is in charge of handling one argument of the TAF. Synchronisation between these agents is provided through the use of sleep constructs that handle time lapsing. In the initial configuration, the shared memory is empty (F = h{}, {}i). sleep(9) → (add({a}, {(b, a), (d, a)}) → (sleep(30) → (rmv({a}, {}) → (sleep(18) → (add({a}, {(b, a), (d, a)}) → (sleep(15) → (rmv({a}, {}) → success))))))) k sleep(29) → (add({b}, {(b, a), (c, b)}) → (sleep(20) → (rmv({b}, {}) → success))) k sleep(19) → (add({c}, {(c, b)}) → (sleep(20) → (rmv({c}, {}) → (sleep(3) → (add({c}, {(c, b)}) → (sleep(10) → (rmv({c}, {}) → (sleep(3) → (add({c}, {(c, b)}) → (sleep(10) → (rmv({c}, {}) → success))))))))))) k sleep(46) → (add({d}, {(d, a), (e, d)}) → (sleep(18) → (rmv({d}, {}) → success))) k add({e}, {(e, d)}) → (sleep(43) → (rmv({e}, {}) → success)) Table 5. tcla program realising the TAF of Figure 3 where each agent handles one argument. 5 Related Work This kind of frameworks has been studied from the point of view of dynamics in works like [13,24], where the authors investigate the consequences brought by modifications on AFs. Given the very nature of argumentation, it is reasonable to assume that the interaction between interacting entities (being them people or synthetic agents) are regulated by the passing of time [21,22]. Timed Abstract Dialectical Frameworks (tADFs) are introduced in [2] to cope with acceptance conditions changing over time. Differently form TAFs, which extend classical AFs with the notion of time intervals, tADFs use generic statements that subsumes arguments and relations (not only including attacks, but also, for instance, supports). Therefore, tADFs are not suitable for being modelled through tcla processes, which, instead, relies on AFs. 6 Conclusion and Future Work In this paper, we introduced tcla, an extension of cla in which time is taken into account in the form of timeouts on expressions. We used maximal paral- lelism to realise simultaneous execution of actions carried forward by different agents. We presented the operational semantics, and showed examples of how to instantiate TAF by using our language. As future work, we would like to study time-dependent notions of acceptability. We could introduce operators for checking if a given argument is acceptable in all (or in some) instants of time. Quantitative temporal operators could, then, be defined to check acceptability only in given intervals. We are also planning to provide a working implementa- tion of tcla able to aid research and serve for application purposes. References 1. Baroni, P., Caminada, M., Giacomin, M.: An introduction to argumentation semantics. Knowl. Eng. Rev. 26(4), 365–410 (2011), https://doi.org/10.1017/ S0269888911000166 2. Baumann, R., Heinrich, M.: Timed abstract dialectical frameworks: A simple translation-based approach. In: Prakken, H., Bistarelli, S., Santini, F., Tatic- chi, C. (eds.) Computational Models of Argument - Proceedings of COMMA 2020, Perugia, Italy, September 4-11, 2020. Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence and Applications, vol. 326, pp. 103–110. IOS Press (2020), https://doi.org/10.3233/ FAIA200496 3. Berry, G., Gonthier, G.: The esterel synchronous programming language: Design, semantics, implementation. Sci. Comput. Program. 19(2), 87–152 (1992), https: //doi.org/10.1016/0167-6423(92)90005-V 4. Bistarelli, S., Gabbrielli, M., Meo, M.C., Santini, F.: Timed soft concurrent con- straint programs: An interleaved and a parallel approach. Theory Pract. Log. Pro- gram. 15(6), 743–782 (2015), https://doi.org/10.1017/S1471068414000106 5. Bistarelli, S., Taticchi, C.: A concurrent language for argumentation. In: Fazz- inga, B., Furfaro, F., Parisi, F. (eds.) Proceedings of the Workshop on Ad- vances In Argumentation In Artificial Intelligence 2020, Online, November 25-26, 2020. CEUR Workshop Proceedings, vol. 2777, pp. 75–89. CEUR-WS.org (2020), http://ceur-ws.org/Vol-2777/paper67.pdf 6. Bistarelli, S., Taticchi, C.: Introducing a tool for concurrent argumentation. In: Faber, W., Friedrich, G., Gebser, M., Morak, M. (eds.) Logics in Artificial Intelli- gence - 17th European Conference, JELIA 2021, Virtual Event, May 17-20, 2021, Proceedings. Lecture Notes in Computer Science, vol. 12678, pp. 18–24. Springer (2021), https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-75775-5 2 7. Bistarelli, S., Taticchi, C.: A unifying four-state labelling semantics for bridging abstract argumentation frameworks and belief revision. In: Proceedings of the 22nd Italian Conference on Theoretical Computer Science, Bologna, Italy, September 13-15, 2021. CEUR Workshop Proceedings, CEUR-WS.org (2021), to appear 8. de Boer, F.S., Gabbrielli, M., Meo, M.C.: A timed concurrent constraint language. Inf. Comput. 161(1), 45–83 (2000), https://doi.org/10.1006/inco.1999.2879 9. de Boer, F.S., Gabbrielli, M., Meo, M.C.: Proving correctness of timed concurrent constraint programs. ACM Trans. Comput. Log. 5(4), 706–731 (2004), https:// doi.org/10.1145/1024922.1024926 10. Budán, M.C., Lucero, M.J.G., Chesñevar, C.I., Simari, G.R.: Modeling time and valuation in structured argumentation frameworks. Inf. Sci. 290, 22–44 (2015), https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ins.2014.07.056 11. Busi, N., Gorrieri, R., Zavattaro, G.: Process calculi for coordination: From linda to javaspaces. In: Rus, T. (ed.) Algebraic Methodology and Software Technology. 8th International Conference, AMAST 2000, Iowa City, Iowa, USA, May 20-27, 2000, Proceedings. Lecture Notes in Computer Science, vol. 1816, pp. 198–212. Springer (2000), https://doi.org/10.1007/3-540-45499-3 16 12. Caminada, M.: On the issue of reinstatement in argumentation. In: Fisher, M., van der Hoek, W., Konev, B., Lisitsa, A. (eds.) Logics in Artificial Intelligence, 10th European Conference, JELIA 2006, Liverpool, UK, September 13-15, 2006, Proceedings. Lecture Notes in Computer Science, vol. 4160, pp. 111–123. Springer (2006), https://doi.org/10.1007/11853886 11 13. Cayrol, C., de Saint-Cyr, F.D., Lagasquie-Schiex, M.: Change in abstract argumen- tation frameworks: Adding an argument. J. Artif. Intell. Res. 38, 49–84 (2010), https://doi.org/10.1613/jair.2965 14. Cobo, M.L., Martı́nez, D.C., Simari, G.R.: On admissibility in timed abstract argumentation frameworks. In: Coelho, H., Studer, R., Wooldridge, M.J. (eds.) ECAI 2010 - 19th European Conference on Artificial Intelligence, Lisbon, Portu- gal, August 16-20, 2010, Proceedings. Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence and Ap- plications, vol. 215, pp. 1007–1008. IOS Press (2010), https://doi.org/10.3233/ 978-1-60750-606-5-1007 15. Cobo, M.L., Martı́nez, D.C., Simari, G.R.: On semantics in dynamic argumentation frameworks. In: XVIII Congreso Argentino de Ciencias de la Computación (2013), http://sedici.unlp.edu.ar/handle/10915/31428 16. Dung, P.M.: On the acceptability of arguments and its fundamental role in non- monotonic reasoning, logic programming and n-person games. Artif. Intell. 77(2), 321–358 (1995), https://doi.org/10.1016/0004-3702(94)00041-X 17. Halbwachs, N., Lagnier, F., Ratel, C.: Programming and verifying real-time sys- tems by means of the synchronous data-flow language LUSTRE. IEEE Trans. Software Eng. 18(9), 785–793 (1992), https://doi.org/10.1109/32.159839 18. Harel, D.: Statecharts: A visual formalism for complex systems. Sci. Comput. Pro- gram. 8(3), 231–274 (1987), https://doi.org/10.1016/0167-6423(87)90035-9 19. Hoare, C.A.R.: Communicating sequential processes. Commun. ACM 21(8), 666– 677 (1978), https://doi.org/10.1145/359576.359585 20. Le Guernic, P., Gautier, T., Le Borgne, M., Le Maire, C.: Programming real-time applications with signal. Proc. IEEE 79(9), 1321–1336 (1991), https://doi.org/10. 1109/5.97301 21. Mann, N., Hunter, A.: Argumentation using temporal knowledge. In: Besnard, P., Doutre, S., Hunter, A. (eds.) Computational Models of Argument: Proceed- ings of COMMA 2008, Toulouse, France, May 28-30, 2008. Frontiers in Arti- ficial Intelligence and Applications, vol. 172, pp. 204–215. IOS Press (2008), http://www.booksonline.iospress.nl/Content/View.aspx?piid=9281 22. Marcos, M.J., Falappa, M.A., Simari, G.R.: Dynamic argumentation in abstract dialogue frameworks. In: McBurney, P., Rahwan, I., Parsons, S. (eds.) Argu- mentation in Multi-Agent Systems - 7th International Workshop, ArgMAS 2010, Toronto, ON, Canada, May 10, 2010 Revised, Selected and Invited Papers. Lec- ture Notes in Computer Science, vol. 6614, pp. 228–247. Springer (2010), https: //doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-21940-5 14 23. Milner, R.: A Calculus of Communicating Systems, Lecture Notes in Computer Science, vol. 92. Springer (1980), https://doi.org/10.1007/3-540-10235-3 24. Rotstein, N.D., Moguillansky, M.O., Falappa, M.A., Garcı́a, A.J., Simari, G.R.: Argument theory change: Revision upon warrant. In: Besnard, P., Doutre, S., Hunter, A. (eds.) Computational Models of Argument: Proceedings of COMMA 2008, Toulouse, France, May 28-30, 2008. Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence and Applications, vol. 172, pp. 336–347. IOS Press (2008), http://www.booksonline. iospress.nl/Content/View.aspx?piid=9292 25. Saraswat, V.A., Jagadeesan, R., Gupta, V.: Timed default concurrent constraint programming. J. Symb. Comput. 22(5/6), 475–520 (1996), https://doi.org/10. 1006/jsco.1996.0064 26. Saraswat, V.A., Rinard, M.C.: Concurrent constraint programming. In: Allen, F.E. (ed.) Conference Record of the Seventeenth Annual ACM Symposium on Principles of Programming Languages, San Francisco, California, USA, 1990. pp. 232–245. ACM Press (1990), https://doi.org/10.1145/96709.96733