=Paper= {{Paper |id=Vol-3069/longpaper03 |storemode=property |title=Towards Ethical and Sustainable Technology-Supported Ageing at Home in Finland – KATI Programme |pdfUrl=https://ceur-ws.org/Vol-3069/FP_03.pdf |volume=Vol-3069 |authors=Heidi Anttila,Marketta Niemelä,Minna Anttila,Satu Pekkarinen,Jaana Hallamaa,Jani Koskinen }} ==Towards Ethical and Sustainable Technology-Supported Ageing at Home in Finland – KATI Programme== https://ceur-ws.org/Vol-3069/FP_03.pdf
       Proceedings of the Conference on Technology Ethics 2021 - Tethics 2021




 Towards Ethical and Sustainable Technology-Supported
    Ageing at Home in Finland – KATI Programme

                                           Full paper


 Heidi Anttila1, Marketta Niemelä2, Minna Anttila1, Satu Pekkarinen3, Jaana Hallamaa4
                                 and Jani Koskinen5
                  1 Finnish Institute for Health and Welfare, Helsinki, Finland
              2 VTT Technical Research Centre of Finland Ltd, Tampere, Finland
                                3 LUT University, Lahti, Finland
                           4 University of Helsinki, Helsinki, Finland
                              5 University of Turku, Turku, Finland


                                       1
                                        heidi.anttila@thl.fi



        Abstract. The population of Finland is ageing with greater demand for health
        and social care; homecare workers are over-burdened with keeping up with this
        change whilst ageing themselves. Technology is seen as one of the most
        promising solutions to tackling these challenges. In the national KATI
        programme, six regional projects will implement technology solutions and adopt
        new technology-based practices in a coordinated manner to support the ageing of
        older people at home as well as the homecare professionals and services. In this
        article, we give an overview of the variety of technology solutions being
        implemented and the first ethical questions that have been raised by the projects
        in the early phase. Thereafter, we highlight three different theoretical approaches
        that support the ethical and sustainable technology implementation advanced by
        the programme. The approaches 1) emphasize the holistic perspective on the
        health of the older person and the method of discourse ethics to seek for
        consensus about the technology solutions, 2) learn from safety research and the
        change theory for better ethical design of AI systems, and 3) analyse the
        technology implementations and the programme from a systemic perspective
        within the framework of socio-technological transition. Our expectation is that
        the approaches will provide theoretical tools and heuristics that can be used to
        ensure that the ultimate goal of the KATI programme, a national, continuing
        collaborative model of technology-supported ageing and care of older people at
        home, will be ethical and sustainable.

        Keywords: ageing, home, technology, AI, ethics




                    Copyright © 2021 for this paper by its authors.                           34
Use permitted under Creative Commons License Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0)
       Proceedings of the Conference on Technology Ethics 2021 - Tethics 2021




 1      Introduction

 Finland is one of the fastest ageing countries in the world. Although ageing people are
 healthier compared to earlier decades, the Finnish workforce, care professionals among
 them, are getting older. People are expected to work longer and retire later, but
 simultaneously, there is a lack of care workers. The economy is facing challenges due
 to increasing service needs and the weakening dependency ratio. Among earlier
 governmental strategies and programmes, the recent technology policy report
 (Technology Advisory Board 2021) underlines the better utilization of technology as
 the most promising solution for the sustainability challenge created by the ageing
 population. There is an urgent need to apply new technologies, data and artificial
 intelligence (AI), and digitalization of services to prevent diseases, support ageing at
 home as long as possible and increase the effectiveness of early-phase care.
    Finland is not alone but the sustainable provision of elderly care is a topic of debate
 in most welfare states (Essink 2012). The debate mainly relates to quality and
 affordability of care.
    Digitalization and the implementation of technologies in elderly care are expected
 to play an increasing role in meeting the anticipated sustainability gap in elderly care
 services (e.g. Kapadia et al. 2015; Malanowski 2008; Peine et al. 2015). Implementing
 these technologies entails a range of challenges, including a lack of suitable
 technologies and immature existing ones (Pekkarinen, Melkas & Hyypiä 2019).
 However, to a great extent, the challenges are related not only to the technologies alone
 but to their integration into the user contexts, such as the services in which they are
 used. In particular, the ethical aspects of the wide technology integration into care
 services should be of interest. The major ethical issues concern, for instance, a sense of
 autonomy, human dignity, informed consent – particularly in the case of cognitive
 impairment, data management issues, affordability and distributive justice (potential
 socio-economic disparities) and impacts of technology use on human contact and
 empathy (see e.g. Wangmo et al. 2019; Niemelä et al. 2021).
    This article introduces a governmental programme called ‘Smart Ageing and Care
 at Home’ (‘KATI’ for the Finnish Acronym) to systematically and purposefully
 advance the implementation of new technologies and digital services for well-being,
 ageing and care of older people at home in Finland. The programme steers six regional
 projects that implement new technologies in services supporting ageing at home and
 home care. The projects themselves already raised some ethical questions in their early
 phases. The programme aims to bring these into the public discussion.
    The programme is supported by an Ethical Advisory Board of expert members that
 bring different ethical and scientific approaches to ensure the ethical and sustainable
 technology implementation advanced by the programme. The approaches concern the
 holistic perspective on the health of the older person and the importance of engaging
 older persons and professionals in the development, the challenges in the current design
 of ethically sound AI systems and services, and the changing practices of ageing at
 home and care services as socio-technical transition. In the discussion, we analyse how
 these approaches support developing the KATI programme towards a continuing
 national-level practice of collaboration, learning and sharing of experiences and




                    Copyright © 2021 for this paper by its authors.                           35
Use permitted under Creative Commons License Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0)
       Proceedings of the Conference on Technology Ethics 2021 - Tethics 2021




 knowledge to ensure the sustainable, ethical and systematic adoption of technologies in
 the ageing society.


 2      A national programme to support well-being, ageing and care
        at home with new technologies (KATI programme)

 The main goal of the KATI programme is to advance and support the integration of
 new technologies into care services for older adults as well as independent living in
 Finland. Utilizing technologies is embedded in the quality recommendation to improve
 the well-being of older people and renew services (Ministry of Social Affairs and
 Health 2020). The programme itself is a coordinating activity that steers six regional
 projects across seven regions in Finland (Figure 1) to reform the services of living at
 home and home care with technology. The project consortia include municipalities or
 associations of municipalities, actors from both the third and private sectors, and
 universities as partners. The projects follow their own regional plans for technology
 deployments under and in collaboration with the coordination body from the Finnish
 Institute for Health and Welfare (THL). The Technical Research Centre of Finland Ltd
 (VTT) participates as an expert of technology solutions.




 Fig. 1. The regional KATI projects on a map of Finland. The number in the circle refers to the
         population coverage of the project in the county.




                    Copyright © 2021 for this paper by its authors.                               36
Use permitted under Creative Commons License Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0)
       Proceedings of the Conference on Technology Ethics 2021 - Tethics 2021




    The regional projects carry out pilots and deployments of various technology
 devices, applications, services and systems. The projects also use technology to collect
 health-related data to be used in care services to support independent and safe living at
 home. The projects co-develop by engaging the users in piloting and adopting
 technologies together with independent older adults, homecare customers, family
 members and care professionals. Moreover, the projects educate and train homecare
 professionals for technology use; develop new care work roles, procurement processes,
 support services and registries for devices and application; and produce health
 technology assessments by using the national Digi-HTA criteria and procedure
 (Haverinen et al. 2019). Overall, the programme encourages the projects to co-develop
 with the stakeholders, involve end users in the early phases to plan the deployment and
 use of technology solutions, and ensure the solutions’ ethics. The vision of the KATI
 programme is illustrated below (Figure 2).




 Fig. 2. The KATI programme vision.

    All projects participate in impact assessment coordinated by THL and VTT. The
 impact assessment of technology systems will be done in a multi-perspective way. The
 focus will be on well-being at home, care professionals and work, costs, processes and
 infrastructure to utilize technology, technology aspects such as feasibility, integrability
 and scalability, business and innovation, and ethics.
    The KATI programme is funded by The Ministry of Social Affairs and Health for
 the years 2020–2023. It is part of the Horizontal National Programme on Ageing 2030
 (Ministry of Social Affairs and Health 2020), which supports good health and
 functional capacity of older people. In addition, KATI is part of the national welfare
 development strategies and implements home living measures of the Well-being and
 Health AI and Robotics Programme (THL 2020). In total, the programme and projects
 have a budget of approximately 10 million euros.




                    Copyright © 2021 for this paper by its authors.                            37
Use permitted under Creative Commons License Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0)
          Proceedings of the Conference on Technology Ethics 2021 - Tethics 2021




 3         Technology solutions and ethical concerns in the KATI
           regional projects

 The KATI projects were launched in February 2020. The overview of the technology
 solutions that are being implemented by the KATI projects has been collected in two
 phases. In online discussions with the KATI projects in the latter phase, we also
 enquired if the project had ethical worries in mind related to the technologies. The
 ethical concerns we raise in this chapter are based on this project input and do not
 systematically cover all ethical concerns related to the technologies in KATI.
    First, in February–March 2020, we arranged a survey for the regions to collect
 information about the technologies they were planning to pilot, adopt or strengthen in
 their KATI project. The survey data were collected as an Excel table from each region
 (the local project coordinator). The table also included questions about expected pilots,
 level of usage, integration into other systems, scalability and support services related to
 each single technology mentioned by the region.
    The aggregated data include dozens of different technology solutions. The most
 popular solutions are various monitoring (e.g. sleep, activity, falling, nutrition) and
 remote health measurements, Internet of Things (IoT) and integration platforms with
 data collected at home, and AI analytics. In Table 1, we have categorized the
 technologies into seven groups.

                  Table 1. Technology solutions to be adopted in the KATI projects

     Solution category                      Examples

     Remote health measurements       Measurements of vital signs or weight at home are
     (attached to the older person)   automatically transferred to care information systems

     Monitoring technologies          Sleep, activity and nutrition monitoring

                                      Wearable safety solution with GPS localization; medicine-
     Safety-increasing solutions      dispensing robot and medicine reminder; monitoring
                                      falling or risk of falling

     Solutions supporting social
                                      Virtual peer groups and coffee groups, social robot
     activity

     Technologies installed in the    Home condition measurements: temperature, humidity,
     apartment                        lights; safety monitoring system at home

                                      Electronic homecare optimizing system; home and remote
     Technologies for care
                                      rehabilitation solutions, exoskeletons, virtual homecare or
     professionals
                                      consultation visits, Virtual Reality–based training

                                      Data from devices, applications and services at home are
   IoT and integration platforms      collected in a platform to be further analysed by care
                                      professional or AI




                    Copyright © 2021 for this paper by its authors.                                 38
Use permitted under Creative Commons License Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0)
        Proceedings of the Conference on Technology Ethics 2021 - Tethics 2021




     Second, in May 2020, we arranged online meetings with each project to discuss the
 first months of the project and elaborate on plans for piloting and implementations. In
 this phase, we found that the projects were starting the implementations somewhat
 slower than we initially expected, and many pilots and implementations were scheduled
 for the next autumn or even the next year. Nevertheless, we collected information about
 the plans related to pilots, purchases, support and training services and expected
 impacts and challenges of the technologies and their use. We also asked the projects
 whether they have already identified ethical questions related to the technologies. The
 projects named four types of worries that they perceived as being ethical (Table 2).

                       Table 2. Ethical worries raised in the KATI projects
 Ethical worry                                                     Ethical values at stake

 When must there be a physical homecare visit and when is a        An issue of expert knowledge
 remote visit sufficient? A professional can judge that remote     vs (recognition of) patient’s
 care is enough, but the relatives or the client are against it.   (perceived) needs
 There are unclear cases.

 Wide 24-hour monitoring strives for safe, independent living      Many values ranging from
 for the client. Homecare workers as well as relatives should      surveillance to rights of access
 have access to the data. What kind of ethical issues concern      to data
 privacy?

 In remote care, e.g. remote care phone application for the        An issue of autonomy and the
 homecare worker who has the phone in her pocket: How can a        possibility  of   meaningful
 client with memory loss give consent for data viewing and         consent
 sharing?

 Data are widely collected in information systems and can also     Right for data protection and
 be viewed for other purposes (secondary use). How do              security
 customers and relatives experience the monitoring and
 (extensive) utilization of data?

    Based on the data and discussions with the project, it is obvious that homecare
 services with physical visits at the older client’s home are strongly shifting towards
 various technology-enabled remote homecare and health services, to the extent that
 technology-based remote care will be provided as the default service. Thus, we also
 present two case descriptions that highlight challenges in the negotiations of remote
 care, as raised by one KATI project:




                    Copyright © 2021 for this paper by its authors.                                   39
Use permitted under Creative Commons License Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0)
       Proceedings of the Conference on Technology Ethics 2021 - Tethics 2021




     Case 1. The client’s relative refuses to implement and pay for a drug reminder.
 The client has a mild memory disorder. The home services attempted to get her a
 medicine reminder because she is still coping relatively well with her daily activities.
 Her only problem is remembering to take medication, which she sometimes forgets.
 The client still carries out other tasks independently, except for banking matters. The
 client agreed to try the medication reminder. However, her sister refused to implement
 it, arguing that the nurse would no longer visit the client daily. The home services
 suggested that instead of a daily visit, three visits a week should be sufficient after
 implementing the drug reminder, as the visits served no other purpose than to monitor
 medication intake. The sister and the client were also informed that if the medicine is
 not taken, the home care will receive an alert, in which case the customer will be either
 called or visited. The sister refused to implement a drug reminder for the client and will
 not pay a monthly fee of €35 for the drug reminder.
     Case 2. Check-up visits according to the client’s wishes. When returning from the
 hospital department, the client wishes to have a check-up visit, even if there is no need
 for home care. The client and relatives want to check that everything is fine. According
 to the criteria, check-up visits are not possible without a real need. In this situation, a
 video connection to the customer may be offered. If the client does not agree to this or
 does not want a remote connection, he or she will not be provided with a homecare
 service. This easily creates a problem for the caregiver because they want to be ‘good
 caregivers’. At the same time, a strong commitment from the caregiver is required for
 the given criteria. This applies to all other caretakers; they promise check-up visits even
 if there is no justification other than the client’s wish. As a caregiver, it is often difficult
 to refuse a client’s request.
     To summarize, the KATI projects will pilot and implement dozens of various
 technology solutions to support home care and independent living of older adults.
 Monitoring and remote care applications are emphasized (and not, for instance,
 physical robots). It seems that the many single devices, applications and systems
 adopted will also be integrated into IoT and integration platforms that combine different
 health data collected at the client’s home. The platforms may also utilize AI to
 automatically analyse the data and raise (non-critical) alerts. These involve many
 ethical questions. The KATI projects themselves have provided some technology-
 related worries that they perceive as ethical in nature, and it is clear that a more
 systematic ethical review needs to be done on the technologies. In this paper, we start
 by discussing three theoretical approaches that we have initially focused on in order to
 understand and tackle the ethical concerns.


 4      Approaches of ethics and sustainability

 4.1    The older person’s health as ‘homelike being-in-the-world’

 The World Health Organization (2021) has defined health as ‘a state of complete
 physical, mental, and social well-being and not merely the absence of disease or
 infirmity.’ This definition from 1946 is over 70 years old, but it seems we are still failing
 to achieve the spirit of that definition, which is to see human beings as complete




                    Copyright © 2021 for this paper by its authors.                                 40
Use permitted under Creative Commons License Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0)
       Proceedings of the Conference on Technology Ethics 2021 - Tethics 2021




 individuals and not to look at only the biomedical state or let the disease define the
 people. Therefore, there is a need for other viewpoints that respect patients as
 individuals with their own needs, desires, fears and backgrounds.
    For this, we derive the definition of health from Svenaeus (2001), who presents it
 as ‘a homelike being-in-the-world’, a concept based on Heidegger’s being-in-the-world
 in his magnum opus, Being and Time (Heidegger 1929). Svenaeus’ view of being
 focuses on the medical context and gives rich insight from the phenomenology of health
 and hermeneutics of medicine. Svenaeus’ idea is that that we should focus not only on
 medical problems per se but should instead shift focus towards individuals’ experiences
 of their own life and their meaningfulness (see Svenaeus 2001). From this viewpoint,
 as a premise, the individual is healthy if they are homelike with their life and can pursue
 meaningful and personal goals. In the sense of health as homelike being-in-the-world,
 some diseases do not necessarily mean that the patient is not healthy – they may just
 have some medical condition, such as diabetes, that needs to be noted and taken care
 of, if needed. Thus, this definition of health is a good approach for promoting different
 roles in health care so that peoples’ needs are taken into account instead of their being
 treated as mere patients. Koskinen (2010) shows that health, when seen as homelike
 being-in-the-world, is compatible with patient-centredness and patient empowerment –
 issues at the core of the KATI programme.
    However, to be able to create health technologies that support health as homelike
 being-in-the-world, we need to bring the citizens and different professionals together
 to ensure that all needed insight is brought to the table. To be able to find consensus
 about what kind of technology supporting smart ageing and care at home would be
 needed, we need open communication between all stakeholders. Without proper
 communication, some viewpoints will override others, and usually, the weakest part is
 bypassed, which is ethically problematic.
    As an approach to prevent this, we propose to utilize discourse ethics in the KATI
 project. Mingers and Walsham (2010) noted that discourse ethics can be seen as a
 practical ethical approach for developing the information services. Likewise, Stahl
 (2012) supports this idea that discourse ethics – based on Habermasian rational
 discourse – provides a mechanism to consider different moral views and intuitions.
 Discourse ethics (Habermas 1992) is based on rational discourse, which is presented in
 communicative action theory (Habermas 1984, 1987) and further developed in his
 work, Between Facts and Norms (Habermas 1996).
    Rational discourse is based on the view that all stakeholders can participate in
 discourse and that discourse itself is rational (Habermas 1996). All arguments in
 rational discourse are evaluated in terms of how convincing and plausible they are.
 Arguments can be based on logic, ethics or another justified basis. A crucial aspect of
 rational discourse is that no strategic games are allowed: they must be rejected. A
 strategic game is a way of influencing others where some participant is trying to end up
 with an outcome by using an action other than a better argument, and this is not allowed.
 These strategic actions can be bargaining, hidden agendas or use of authority over
 others (James 2003).




                    Copyright © 2021 for this paper by its authors.                            41
Use permitted under Creative Commons License Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0)
       Proceedings of the Conference on Technology Ethics 2021 - Tethics 2021




 4.2    Seeking resources for ethically sound AI systems and services

 Along with the great expectation attached to the design and use of AI systems, there are
 still worries over the negative impacts of the ongoing development. To prevent and
 mitigate the ills, several suggestions for how to design ethically sound AI systems have
 been formulated. The existing AI ethical codes cover a variety of approaches from high
 profile declarations to normative rules of thumb for users and practical checklists for
 designers (Mittelstadt 2019, 501; Jobin, Ienca & Vayena 2019). Two things are
 common to the ethics documents: first, they share the aim to support the ethical design
 of AI, and second, they presuppose that it is possible to formulate AI ethics that will
 serve as the theoretical basis for deducing morally sound practical solutions for AI
 (Morley et al. 2019).
     Evidence from the AI ethics endeavours is rather depressing. Studies show that
 attempts to secure ethical sustainability has not been effective (Hagendorff 2020, 118).
 Both theoretical and practical reasons suggest that the approach to tackle the moral
 problems should be wider than the present conceptions of AI ethics.
     One of the reasons why the current ethical approaches have not been successful is
 that they do not pay enough attention to the specific features of AI. Typically in AI,
 the products and outcomes are not just single devices or services but sets of programs
 and applications within larger, often extremely complex systems. It is not possible to
 extract AI from the rest of the system. Most of the development and applications are
 carried out as commercial enterprises within the market economy. AI is a general
 means that is applicable to almost any human activity, which provides innumerable
 possibilities to employ it. Such features of AI have moral relevance, and they should
 receive due attention in formulations of AI ethics (Boddington 2017, 93).
     To better account for the specific features of AI systems, we need a wider variety of
 resources than just the traditional ethical apparatus characteristic of the current AI
 ethics codes. During the past century, safety research has developed into a rigorous
 academic study that is tightly connected to the empirical reality of hazards and risks.
 There are several useful conceptions within safety studies that could help detrimental
 chains of events from taking place, even when implementing AI into elderly care (see
 Reiman & Oedewald 2008, 39–47 and Hollnagel 2014 about the development).
     The aim of AI design and development is to change people’s lives for the better and
 to positively impact the targeted issues. Recent studies on the factors involved in
 bringing about change and making a desired impact also offer tools for improving the
 ethical quality of AI. The theory of change and the Impact Management Project offer
 methods for organizations and companies to better keep track of the change they intend
 to bring about and the actual effects of their work on reality. Both approaches have their
 starting point in the complexities of the current world, where it is often difficult to plan
 and follow straightforward strategies. In favourable circumstances and with the right
 kinds of measures, the desired change emerges (Weiss 1995; Theory of Change).




                    Copyright © 2021 for this paper by its authors.                             42
Use permitted under Creative Commons License Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0)
       Proceedings of the Conference on Technology Ethics 2021 - Tethics 2021




 4.3    Technology implementation in elderly care transition – the socio-technical
        transition framework

 A central question is how innovations – both technologies and related innovative
 practices – contribute to broader societal changes in an ethically and socially
 sustainable way. This is also an issue to be considered in the KATI programme. To
 respond to this question, systemic views that highlight the relationships of technical,
 human and social aspects are needed. One of these systemic frameworks is the
 framework of socio-technological transition. Because this approach highlights the
 interdependence and mutual adjustments between technological, social, political and
 cultural dimensions (Bugge, Coenen, Marques & Morgan 2017; Smith, Voss & Grin
 2010), it is a fruitful approach in studying processes taking place in the digitalization
 of the elderly care sector. The introduction of technologies into society and the
 development of technological innovations require a deep transition that entails the
 simultaneous development of technologies, service operations and people’s practices
 and mindsets (e.g. Geels 2002, 2005; Truffer & Coenen 2012).
     The multi-level perspective of socio-technical transitions tackles transitions as co-
 evolutionary processes on three interrelated conceptual levels: the socio-technical
 landscape, the socio-technical regime and bottom-level niches. The socio-technical
 regime can be seen as the way services are currently organized regarding
 infrastructures, service structures and products (using both high and low technology).
 It also includes mindset-related issues, such as people’s preferences about the products
 and services they use and consume and related ethical values, the market, public sector
 and policy views, and the responses of such actors to people’s wishes and requirements
 (Pekkarinen et al. 2020). In other words, elderly care is perceived as a socio-technical
 system consisting of services, technologies, science, infrastructures, user preferences
 and cultural meanings as well as ethical values (see Geels 2002).
     Established socio-technical regimes are resistant to change, but transitions take place
 when changes at the landscape level, such as population ageing, exert pressure on the
 regime and make it unstable (Geels & Schot, 2007). The destabilization of the regime
 creates windows of opportunity for niche innovations, which are emerging social or
 technical innovations that differ radically from the products and practices in the
 prevailing socio-technical system and regime (Kemp et al. 1998; Geels 2018).
     The various technologies and technology-based practices created and implemented
 in the KATI programme projects can be viewed as these niches. It may be difficult for
 new technologies to gain ground if they face a mismatch between the existing regime
 and the landscape. Until external circumstances are right, for example, the regime is
 destabilized, creating a window for opportunity for these radical novelties. This is why
 the niche innovations are called ‘seeds for change’ (Geels 2005). Examples of niches
 in social and health care and elderly care include service robots, various monitoring
 devices, technology for self-diagnosis and novel service configurations or care-work
 practices (Pekkarinen et al. 2020). The selection of new technologies and innovative
 practices is more than mere adoption. Users must also integrate novelties into their
 practices, organizations and routines (Geels 2002), and niches frequently collide with
 the regime because of existing practices’ inertia and lock-ins. More than the ‘singular




                    Copyright © 2021 for this paper by its authors.                            43
Use permitted under Creative Commons License Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0)
       Proceedings of the Conference on Technology Ethics 2021 - Tethics 2021




 disruption’ of niches, the question is about ‘system reconfiguration’ (Markard &
 Truffer 2006; Geels 2018). A wider breakthrough is followed by a stabilization and
 new types of structuring. These dynamics and interplay at different levels reinforce
 each other and lead to system changes and transitions (Geels & Kemp 2007).


 5      Discussion

 When adopting new technologies to support ageing and care services at home, the care
 professionals will need to tackle various ethical issues, of which we gave examples in
 Section 3. The KATI programme will raise these into public discussion in order to
 support the regional projects to find acceptable and sustainable solutions, whether based
 on technology or on the renewing practices of care. In addition, we described three
 approaches to ethical and sustainable technology implementation into elderly care.
 First, we introduced a concept of homelike being-in-the-world as a patient-centred and
 participatory approach and how the utilization of discourse ethics can be used to support
 open communication and understanding between all stakeholders. Second, we
 highlighted the theory of change and the Impact Management Project, which offers
 methods for homecare organizations to better keep track of the change they intend to
 bring about and the actual effects of their work on the patients. And third, we discussed
 the framework of socio-technological transition and how bringing several new
 technologies into home care is an evolving ‘system configuration’ where single
 solutions are seeds for a larger socio-technical change.
    The homecare services would benefit from adding these perspectives in their
 practical care ethics in several ways. Every single worry that care professionals identify
 in their everyday work should be collected and discussed. This gives information about
 possible risks and lack of safety and tackling these at early phase increase care ethics
 for each single client situation. Taking the wider perspective and applying the method
 of Discourse Ethics could help to discuss and solve concrete problematic cases. For
 instance, in the two case examples from the KATI projects, the rules and care principles
 of the homecare are not understood either by the relatives, the client or the homecare
 workers. We argue, however, that using the presented principles and methods even
 these problems could be solved. This may require wide discussion from several angles
 and change of viewpoints of all participants.
    Nevertheless, the approaches should work best on the programme level to support
 its development and national coordinating activities towards the sustainable
 technology-supported aging at home. For example, the KATI programme itself can be
 seen as a ‘window of opportunity’ for innovative niche technologies and practices to at
 least be experimented with, if not adopted, in the prevailing homecare service system,
 thus expectedly contributing to a wide-scale systemic change. The approaches provide
 theoretical tools and heuristics that can be used to ensure that the ultimate goal of the
 KATI programme – a national, continuing collaborative model of technology-
 supported ageing and care of older people at home – will be ethical and sustainable.




                    Copyright © 2021 for this paper by its authors.                           44
Use permitted under Creative Commons License Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0)
       Proceedings of the Conference on Technology Ethics 2021 - Tethics 2021




 References
 Boddington, P. (2017). Towards a Code of Ethics for Artificial Intelligence. Artificial
          Intelligence: Foundations, Theory, and Algorithms. Springer International Publishing
          AG. DOI: 10.1007/978-3-319-60648-4
 Bugge, M., Coenen, L., Marques, P., & Morgan, K. (2017). Governing system innovation:
         Assisted living experiments in the UK and Norway. European Planning Studies,
         25(12), 2138–2156.
 Essink, D. R. (2012). Sustainable Health Systems: The Role of Change Agents in Health System
          Innovation. Amsterdam, Netherlands: VU University.
 Geels, F. W. (2002). Technological transitions as evolutionary reconfiguration processes: A
          multi-level perspective and a case-study. Research Policy, 31(8/9), 1257–1274.
 Geels, F. W. (2005). Technological Transitions and System Innovations: A Co-Evolutionary and
           Sociotechnical Analysis, Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar Publishing.
 Geels, F. W. (2018). Disruption and low-carbon system transformation: Progress and new
          challenges in socio-technical transitions research and the Multi-Level Perspective.
          Energy Research & Social Science, 37, 224–231.
 Geels, F. W., & Kemp, R. (2007). Dynamics in socio-technical systems: Typology of change
           processes and contrasting case studies. Technology in Society, 29(4), 441–455.
 Geels, F. W., & Schot, J. W. (2007). Typology of sociotechnical transition pathways. Research
           Policy, 36(3), 399–417.
 Habermas, J (1984). The theory of communicative action, volume 1. Polity Press.
 Habermas, J. (1987). The Theory of Communicative Action: Lifeworld and Systems, a Critique
         of Functionalist Reason, Volume 2, Translated by McCarthy, T. Polity Press.
 Habermas, J. (1992). Discourse Ethics: Notes on a Programme of Philosophical Justification,
         in Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action, J. Habermas (ed.), Cambridge,
         UK: Polity Press, pp. 43-115.
 Habermas, J. (1996). Between facts and norms: contributions to a discourse theory of law and
         democracy. Trans. Rheg William. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
 Hagendorff, T. (2020). The ethics of AI ethics: An evaluation of guidelines. Minds and Machines,
         30, 99–120. DOI: 10.1007/s11023-020-09517-8
 Haverinen, J., Keränen, N., Falkenbach, P., Maijala, A., Kolehmainen, T., & Reponen, J. (2019).
          Digi-HTA: Health technology assessment framework for digital healthcare services.
          Finnish Journal of eHealth and eWelfare,                11(4),     326–341–326–341.
          DOI:10.23996/FJHW.82538
 Heidegger, M. (1927). Originally Sein Und Zeit, Basil Blackwell, Oxford, [Used several
         translations. Main translation: Being and Time by Macquarrie J. and Robinson E.
         1962].
 Hollnagel, E. (2014). Safety-I and Safety-II: The Past and Future of Safety Management. Boca
          Raton, Fl: CRC Press.




                    Copyright © 2021 for this paper by its authors.                                 45
Use permitted under Creative Commons License Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0)
        Proceedings of the Conference on Technology Ethics 2021 - Tethics 2021




 James, M. R. (2003). Communicative action, strategic action, and inter-group dialogue. European
          Journal of Political Theory, 2(2), 157–182.
 Jobin, A., Ienca, M, & Vayena, E. (2019). Artificial intelligence: the global landscape of ethics
           guidelines. Nature Machine Intelligence, 1, 389–399. DOI: 10.1038/s42256-019-0088-
           2
 Kapadia, V., Ariani, A., Li, J., & Ray, P. K. (2015). Emerging ICT implementation issues in aged
          care. International Journal of Medical Informatics, 84(11), 982–900.
 Kemp, R., Schot, J., & Hoogma, R. (1998). Regime shifts to sustainability through processes of
          niche formation: The approach of strategic niche management. Technology Analysis
          and Strategic Management, 10(2), 175–196.
 Koskinen J. (2010). Phenomenological view of health and patient empowerment with Personal
         Health Record, in Suomi R & Ilveskoski I. (Eds.), Proceedings of the Third
         International Conference on well-being in the Information Society (WIS 2010), 111-
         122.
 Malanowski, N. (2008). Matching demand and supply: Future technologies for active ageing in
         Europe. In F. Kohlbacher and C. Herstatt (Eds.). The Silver Market Phenomenon.
         Business Opportunities in an Era of Demographic Change (41–53). Heidelberg,
         Germany: Springer.
 Markard, J., & Truffer, B. (2006). Innovation processes in large technical systems: Market
          liberalization as a driver for radical change? Research Policy, 35(5), 609–625.
 Mingers, J. and Walsham, G. (2010). Toward ethical information systems: The contribution of
          discourse ethics. MIS Quarterly, 34(4):833–854.
 Mittelstadt, B. (2019). Principles alone cannot guarantee ethical AI. Perspectives. Nature
           Machine Intelligence, 1, 501–507. DOI: 10.1038/s42256-019-0114-4 2.6.2021
 Morley, J. & Floridi, L. & Kinsey, L. & Elhalal, A. (2019). From what to how: An initial review
           of publicly available AI ethics tools, methods and research to translate principles into
           practices. Science and engineering ethics, 11 December 2019. arXiv:1905.06876
           DOI:10.1007/s11948-019-00165-5.
 Ministry of Social Affairs and Health (2020). National Programme on Ageing 2030. For an age-
           competent Finland. Publications of the Ministry of Social Affairs and Health, 2020:38.
           Retrieved from: http://urn.fi/URN:ISBN:978-952-00-8431-8 (accessed 30.8.2021)
 Ministry of Social Affairs and Health, Association of Finnish Local and Regional Authorities
          (2020). Quality recommendation to guarantee a good quality of life and improved
          services for older people in 2020–2023 (Finnish and Swedish only). Publications of the
          Ministry of Social Affairs and Health, 2020:29. Retrieved from:
          http://urn.fi/URN:ISBN:978-952-00-5457-1 (accessed 30.8.2021)
 Niemelä, M., Heikkinen, S., Koistinen, P., Laakso, K., Melkas, H., and Kyrki, V. (eds.)
          (2021). Robots and the Future of Welfare Services – A Finnish Roadmap. Aalto
          University publication series CROSSOVER, 4/2021. Retrieved from:
          http://urn.fi/URN:ISBN:978-952-64-0323-6.




                    Copyright © 2021 for this paper by its authors.                                   46
Use permitted under Creative Commons License Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0)
       Proceedings of the Conference on Technology Ethics 2021 - Tethics 2021




 Peine, A., Faulkner, A., Jæger, B., & Moors, E. (2015). Science, technology and the ‘grand
           challenge’ of ageing: Understanding the socio-material constitution of later life.
           Technological Forecasting & Social Change, 93, 1–9.
 Pekkarinen, S., Hennala, L., Tuisku, O., Gustafsson, C., Johansson-Pajala, R-M., Thommes, K.,
          Hoppe, J.A Melkas H. (2020). Embedding care robots into society and practice: Socio-
          technical considerations, Futures, 122.
 Pekkarinen, S., Melkas, H., & Hyypiä, M. (2019). Elderly care and digital services: Toward a
          sustainable sociotechnical transition. In Toivonen, & Saari (Eds.). Human centered
          digitalization and services (pp. 259–284). Singapore: Springer.
 Reiman, T. & Oedewald, P. (2008). Turvallisuuskriittiset organisaatiot: Onnettomuudet,
         kulttuuri ja johtaminen (Safety critical organizations: Accidents, culture and manage-
         ment). Helsinki: Edita.
 Smith, A., Voss, J.-P., & Grin, J. (2010). Innovation studies and sustainability transitions: The
          allure of the multi-level perspective and its challenges. Research Policy, 39(4), 435–
          448.
 Stahl, B. C. (2012). Morality, ethics, and reflection: A categorization of normative is research.
           Journal of the Association for Information Systems, 13(8), 636–656.
 Svenaeus, F. (2001). The Hermeneutics of Medicine and the Phenomenology of Health: Steps
          towards a Philosophy of Medical Practice (2nd revised edition). London: Kluwer
          Academic Publishing.
 Technology Advisory Board (2021). Suomen teknologiapolitiikka 2020-luvulla – Teknologialla
         ja tiedolla maailman kärkeen (Finnish technology policy in 2020s – A global leader
         through technology and information). Publications of the Ministry of Finance 2021:30.
         Retrieved from: http://urn.fi/URN:ISBN:978-952-367-692-3 (accessed 7.6.2021)
 Theory of Change. Retrieved from: https://www.theoryofchange.org/what-is-theory-of-change/
          (accessed 1.6.2021)
 THL (2020). The Well-being and Health Sector’s Artificial Intelligence and Robotics Programme
         (Hyteairo).      Retrieved      from:       https://thl.fi/en/web/thlfi-en/research-and-
         development/research-       and-projects/the-well-being-and-health-sector-s-artificial-
         intelligence-and-robotics-programme- hyteairo- (accessed 30.8.2021)
 Truffer, B., & Coenen, L. (2012). Environmental innovation and sustainability transitions in
           regional studies. Regional Studies, 46(1), 1–21.
 Wangmo, T., Lipps, M., Kressig, R.W., Ienca, M. (2019). Ethical concerns with the use of
        intelligent assistive technology: findings from a qualitative study with professional
        stakeholders. BMC Medical Ethics 20, 98. DOI: 10.1186/s12910-019-0437-z
 Weiss, C. (1995). Nothing as Practical as Good Theory: Exploring Theory-Based Evaluation for
           Comprehensive Community Initiatives for Children and Families. New Approaches to
           Evaluating Community Initiatives. Aspen: Aspen Institute.
 World Health Organisation. (2021). WHO Definition of Health. Retrieved from:
        https://apps.who.int/gb/bd/PDF/bd47/EN/constitution-en.pdf?ua=1 (accessed
        7.6.2021)




                    Copyright © 2021 for this paper by its authors.                                  47
Use permitted under Creative Commons License Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0)